13.02.2013 Views

BOOKS OF RtfiDIfGS - PAHO/WHO

BOOKS OF RtfiDIfGS - PAHO/WHO

BOOKS OF RtfiDIfGS - PAHO/WHO

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

1 Klarman<br />

Intargibl Benefits<br />

- .5 -<br />

Pain, discomfort, and grief are among the costs of illness currently borne, which<br />

constitute the intangible benefits of a program of health services that averts them. The<br />

benefits accrue partly to the patients and partly to their friends, relatives, and society at<br />

large, to the extent that we. take pleasure in the happiness of others. That positive<br />

externai effects in consumption exist is indicated by personal and philanthropic gifts. to<br />

the extent that they are not subsidized by the deductibility provisions of the income<br />

tax (59). Looming even larger is the averted premature loss of human life. Since none of<br />

these effects is traded on the market, none carries a price tag. In attempting to put a value<br />

on averting them the question arises: what would one be willing to pay to avoid them?<br />

In my paper on syphilis (45), 1 estimated willingness to pay for escaping the early and<br />

late manifestations of the disease by examining expenditures incurred in connection with<br />

other diseases that met certain conditions. After consultation with clinicians 1 adopted<br />

psoriasis as the analogue for early syphilis, and terminal cancer as the analogue for its late<br />

stage. The conditions specified were that the expenditures for medical care represented<br />

principally a willingness to pay for freedom from the particular disease, since in neither<br />

case could direct or indirect tangible benefits, as defined above, be realized. To the extent<br />

that payments were made only by the patient (directly or through health insurance),<br />

willingness to pay by others was neglected and total willingness to pay was understated.<br />

Neenan (60) has estimated the consumer benefit of a community chest x-ray program<br />

for tuberculosis. With the help of some fee data indicating willingness to pay, he obtained<br />

very high estimates of value.<br />

Several years have elapsed since intangible benefits were valued. The analogous diseases<br />

approach has not been repeated; this suggests that neither the estimates themselves nor<br />

the procedures for obtaining them have been found useful. One reason is obvious: the<br />

approach is specific, calling for the development of estimates, disease by disease.<br />

A larger body of literature is devoted to the value of human itfe than to the other<br />

types of intangible health benefit. Life insurance holdings are clearly not applicable to<br />

bachelors and jury verdicts are inconsistent (13, p. 37). The implications of public policy<br />

decisions or govemmental spending are difficult to elicit in the absence of information on<br />

the alternatives that faced the decision makers (19). Moreover, such valuation may lack<br />

stability and consistency (24, pp. 133-134).<br />

Schelling(61) has proposed a different approach. He would measure the value of<br />

human life, as distinguished from livelihood, by the arnount people are willing to spend to<br />

buy a specified reduction in the statistical probability of death. Acton (24, p. 258)<br />

applied this approach, and derived an estimate of the value of human life at $28,000. This<br />

amount serves as a substitute for the net value of lost earnings and is not an additional<br />

sum.<br />

I am not sanguine about the applicability of Acton's numerical estimate to the<br />

evaluation of program alternatives. Acton was the first to criticize the defects in his<br />

estimate, including the small size of his sample, and its apparent biases. While these<br />

defects can be remedied in the future, what troubles me is the likelihood that respondents<br />

to this type of question may not grasp its meaning. Do respondents know the actual<br />

probabilities of their dying in the coming year? How is a small-e.g. 1 per cent-reduction<br />

in statistical probability perceived? How much more is a 10 per cent reduction worth<br />

than a 1 per cent reduction? Is it plausible to postulate a strictly linear relationship

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!