04.09.2015 Views

PAVILION

PAVILION

PAVILION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

tage of a semicircular hall, by contrast, is<br />

that at least one person, the speaker, can<br />

see and hear everyone equally well.<br />

However, factions, contradictions and<br />

distances emerge more readily as a<br />

result. Moreover, any lengthening of the<br />

semicircle leads to the formation of blind<br />

spots from which it is impossible to see or<br />

be seen.<br />

If parliamentary architecture is to take<br />

account of democratic principles it must<br />

enable all the lawmakers to make themselves<br />

heard and understood and to communicate<br />

their views. The tension<br />

between the architecture, which prescribes<br />

a certain use and certain patterns<br />

of behavior, and the debates in a parliament<br />

bestows different powers on the<br />

parliamentary players. Anyone occupying<br />

the Speaker’s chair or a seat on the government<br />

benches or controlling what is<br />

going on behind the scenes obviously<br />

has more power than a backbencher. But<br />

it is not just the members of a parliament<br />

who have power. The architecture does,<br />

too. It determines not only how the members<br />

of the parliament can communicate<br />

with one another but also who speaks to<br />

whom and about what. It determines who<br />

sees and hears what. Moreover, it determines<br />

whose voice counts. In a circular<br />

chamber it is possible and sensible for<br />

everyone to speak from his or her seat.<br />

This makes it clear that a single opinion is<br />

being expressed and that just one of<br />

many possible viewpoints is being contributed<br />

to the overall picture. If there is a<br />

rostrum, however, the speaker addresses<br />

the audience in a semicircle, having no<br />

choice but to take up the sole legitimate<br />

speaking position.<br />

The wrestling over parliamentary architecture<br />

shows that the ability to speak<br />

and make decisions depends on the<br />

opportunity to participate, to be present,<br />

visible and audible. The existence of<br />

political conflicts, the admission of various<br />

persons (genders, generations), the<br />

lively debate, the audibility of many different<br />

voices, the articulation of approval or<br />

disapproval can be hindered or reinforced<br />

by architectural means.<br />

Ever since the French Revolution the<br />

hegemony of “representative democracy”<br />

has rested on the semicircular model of<br />

the classical Roman theater. The seating<br />

arrangements put the focus on the rostrum.<br />

According to the theory, it is performances<br />

in the form of monologues that<br />

gives shape and a voice to the people,<br />

who for their part subsequently express<br />

their will through their representatives.<br />

Wherever “representative democracy”<br />

has been introduced, it was not the result<br />

of a plebiscite but of a decree issued by a<br />

parliament, for which (on average) hundreds<br />

of members were needed. The<br />

number of representatives derives not<br />

from the size of the population or from the<br />

statistical average of the supposed political<br />

elite but quite simply from the number<br />

of seats in this type of theater.<br />

III.<br />

The key criterion of the political in traditional<br />

political philosophy would appear<br />

to be a decision based on rational consideration.<br />

This criterion could be met<br />

behind closed doors. Is not the holding of<br />

a debate pure sham? Why do we need a<br />

parliament? Why is the public space<br />

important for political decisions? Does<br />

the semicircle of members of a parlia-<br />

ment constitute a satisfactory audience?<br />

Is a television broadcast of the proceedings<br />

sufficient or is a public only properly<br />

established when it can articulate itself<br />

and voice criticism and when anyone who<br />

wishes can take part?<br />

In answering these questions it is important<br />

to distinguish between a public<br />

space that collects or interrupts and the<br />

political space that forms part of the<br />

social space. The social arises from<br />

spaces of ordered communication and<br />

presumes that an assembly exists. The<br />

political space uses aesthetic, disciplinary<br />

and biological means to put people<br />

in certain positions. It is characterized by<br />

conditions of control, by the markings of<br />

appropriation and by distancing mechanisms,<br />

which identify the subjects and<br />

stabilize them in the hierarchical<br />

(genealogical, and the like) relationships<br />

they have with each other (for example<br />

hospitals, schools, prisons, parliaments).<br />

In the political sphere power can therefore<br />

be exercised and reproduced,<br />

whereas the public space cannot be cordoned<br />

off and controlled. On the contrary,<br />

it is not subject to any unequivocal system<br />

of perception, permitting a wide<br />

range of insights, allowing anonymity and<br />

opening up channels of communication<br />

for new participants, new distributions<br />

and new questions.<br />

The public gallery is an alien element in<br />

the classical theatrical architecture in<br />

which the members of a parliament find<br />

themselves. Like a wedge, it pries open<br />

the closed nature of the parliamentary<br />

system of perception and participation.<br />

The penetration of the public into the<br />

political space can only be explained by<br />

the radical democratic currents of the<br />

French Revolution.<br />

Proceedings in the English Parliament<br />

once took place behind closed doors if for<br />

no other purpose than to pursue policies<br />

directed against the king and his court. “I<br />

spy strangers,” was the formal call for the<br />

doors of the House of Commons to be<br />

closed and for any potential listeners to<br />

be removed.<br />

From the point of view of enlightened<br />

analysis there is no reason why the journalistic<br />

debate should not relate exclusively<br />

to texts, for instance to announcements<br />

made by a parliament or government<br />

followed by discussion of them in<br />

specialist journals. Quite clearly, however,<br />

that is not a satisfactory situation for<br />

either the press or the public. Reports on<br />

parliamentary activities and daily events<br />

can reinforce or undermine the sovereignty<br />

of a parliament. The physical presence<br />

of watching journalists brings quite<br />

different forces into play. In 1798, for<br />

instance, the British secretary of war,<br />

William Windham, complained about the<br />

continual reporting and warned that press<br />

coverage of the parliamentary debates<br />

would inevitably transform the English<br />

constitution from a representative one<br />

into “an entirely democratic one”. And in<br />

1826 Wellington wrote: “Discussions with<br />

open doors, and the publication of the<br />

discussions of a Legislative Assembly,<br />

however desirable, are not absolutely<br />

necessary for the existence of freedom or<br />

good government in any country. Our<br />

own regulations, and the principles on<br />

which the discussions of our Houses of<br />

Parliament are founded and carried on,<br />

are that they are private and not to be<br />

made public.”<br />

But in what sense can discussions<br />

[178]<br />

[179]

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!