01.05.2013 Views

QUANTUM METAPHYSICS - E-thesis

QUANTUM METAPHYSICS - E-thesis

QUANTUM METAPHYSICS - E-thesis

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Even if, at first sight, chance appears to be the very negation of determinism, it should be noted<br />

that chance also has its laws, and accidents emerge from pre-existing conditions. Games of<br />

chance do not follow the Newtonian type of law but follow statistical laws instead: they are<br />

statistically determined. On such a basis, it can even be argued that chance is not alien to<br />

determinism. Chance may in fact be a peculiar type of determination, because the principle of<br />

lawfulness does not require that every individual phenomenon should always occur in exactly the<br />

same way. Universal lawfulness is not committed to a specific form of determinism such as<br />

causal determinism or mechanical determinism. It is consistent with individual exceptions, with<br />

occurrences in a given low percentage of cases. 564 Bohr highlighted the fact that the determinism<br />

of classical physics was only an idealisation suitable for addressing situations at the macroscopic<br />

level whereas Wolfgang Pauli was fond of saying that quantum theory is indeterministic and that<br />

individual events "slip through" the net of physics.<br />

While predictability is often taken to be a symptom of causality, or causation is even defined in<br />

terms of predictability, this may be unwarranted. Predictability is an epistemological category<br />

dependent on our knowledge, whereas causation is a mode of behaviour of things in the real<br />

world, an ontological category. 565 The common equating of causality with predictability is linked<br />

to the problem concerning measurements in quantum physics. In classical physics, the process of<br />

measurement could be described objectively from an external viewpoint by comparing the result<br />

yielded by measurement to a space-time portrayal or a model created by theory. Quantum theory,<br />

on the other hand, does not generate a model for the process of measurement. When the theory is<br />

applied to both the measuring apparati and to microscopic objects, the final state of the system<br />

will be a superposition of state vectors. This does not, however, represent a definite observable<br />

state. The final state should be a so called mixed state, but no transformations map initial pure<br />

states into final mixed states. The theory is thus not able to describe how it is possible to proceed<br />

from the uncertain and non-classical quantum realm to the stable and separable world of<br />

everyday experience. 566<br />

564<br />

Bunge 1959, 13-14, 23. If chance has a place in the framework of determinism in the general sense, quantum<br />

theory does not lead to the bankrupty of determinism. Bunge sees as a widespread misconception that causality is<br />

regarded as necessarily mechanistic and that, conversely, mechanism necessarily entails causality. The mere<br />

existence of the Platonic and Aristotelian systems shows that causality need not be mechanistic. Mechanistic<br />

philosophy from Galileo to the Newtonians restricted causes to forces contrary to the richer but chimerical forms of<br />

causation imagined by Aristotle and his innumerable commentators. In actual fact, contrary to the causal system of<br />

Aristotle in which every motion requires a cause, Newton´s principle of inertia is openly non-causal and can be seen<br />

as a restricted version of the principle of self-movement. Bunge 1959, 107-110, 116.<br />

565<br />

Bunge 1959, 326-327.<br />

566<br />

Murdoch 1987, 113.<br />

214

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!