01.05.2013 Views

QUANTUM METAPHYSICS - E-thesis

QUANTUM METAPHYSICS - E-thesis

QUANTUM METAPHYSICS - E-thesis

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Democritus’ atomic doctrine, which had been rediscovered during sudies of antique literature,<br />

was a source of inspiration to Galileo 30 years before it began to gain currency with other<br />

thinkers. Galileo did not, however, regard the movement of atoms as random, since to him all<br />

parts of the universe were ruled by laws. In some of his writings, Galileo employed expressions<br />

used by Epicurus, and from Democritus he adopted the concept of primary and secondary<br />

qualities. The primary properties of things such as size, shape, number and motion had their<br />

source in the properties of atoms and could be measured. The secondary, qualitative properties<br />

such as colour, taste and odour were considered to be subjective phenomena of secondary<br />

importance that arose in the human sense organs and were dependent on the primary qualities.<br />

When the real world was simply a succession of atomic motions in mathematical continuity, man<br />

was in a way eliminated from it. Only the primary qualities were real and our knowledge of<br />

objects was mediated by the secondary qualities arising in the senses. 191<br />

Galileo is generally regarded as the father of natural science. In his time, Galileo’s proposition<br />

that the behaviour of material objects could be explained by referring only to physical and<br />

mechanistic factors represented a completely new way of thinking: quantitative relationships did<br />

not occupy a predominant position in peripatetic philosophy. In contrast to Plato and Pythagoras,<br />

who also highlighted the role of mathematics, the object of research for natural scientists of the<br />

modern time has clearly been, as it was for Aristotle, the visible world and the changes<br />

observable in it. 192 By analysing the quantitative and measurable changes taking place in space<br />

and time, natural science has truly been able to discover general laws which control phenomena.<br />

In a brief period Galileo was able to refute experimentally many of the aspects of Aristotle’s<br />

physics which had been criticised but not empirically disproved by many philosophers.<br />

Observations and repeatable experiments revealed laws of nature which could be stated in exact<br />

mathematical form. When portraying the epoch-making characteristics of the Galilean method, it<br />

has been repeatedly pointed out that as a consequence of the new natural science, ‘natural laws’<br />

no longer meant “qualitates occultae” which were derived from the hidden qualities of things,<br />

but dependent relationships governed by laws which could be stated as mathematical<br />

190 Dijksterhuis 1986, 348-352.<br />

191 White 1998, 38-39. Trusted 1991, 52. Collingwood 1960, 94-102. Burtt 1980, 83-84, 98-99. Although Galileo’s<br />

thou ghts are reconciliable with the fundamental principle of the mechanistic interpretation of nature his conceptions<br />

of the void form a curious blend of ideas originating from medieval physics. His idea of the cosmos as a beautifully<br />

and efficiently-organized whole was perhaps too vivid for him to be satisfied by the notion of atoms in an infinite<br />

void. Dijksterhuis 1986, 419-424.<br />

192 Trusted 1991, 61-62.<br />

78

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!