01.05.2013 Views

QUANTUM METAPHYSICS - E-thesis

QUANTUM METAPHYSICS - E-thesis

QUANTUM METAPHYSICS - E-thesis

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Like Kepler, Galileo had established a reputation as a mathematician at an early stage in his<br />

academic career. At the age of 25, he was appointed to the position of professor of mathematics<br />

at Pisa, and three years later, in 1592, he moved to Padova. There he studied falling bodies and<br />

developed his epoch-making laws of motion, which proved that Aristotle’s ideas concerning the<br />

motion of bodies were incorrect. With the help of observations and accurate measurements,<br />

Galileo concentrated on studying how objects actually moved in reality. Others before Galileo<br />

had asked why heavy bodies fall, but he also subjected terrestial motion to precise mathematical<br />

study. His first concern was not to explain, but to describe. Even more than to Kepler, nature<br />

presented herself to Galileo as a simple orderly system. He was continually astonished at the<br />

marvellous manner in which natural happenings folloved the principles of geometry. Aristotle,<br />

like the preceding traditions of natural philosophy, was concerned with searching for the cause or<br />

purpose of motion. He believed that objects were seeking their natural positions from which they<br />

could not be removed except by an external force, but Galileo now concluded that while objects<br />

could indeed be at rest if nothing was forcing them to move, they could also be moving at<br />

constant velocity. 189<br />

In contrast to everyday observation, no force was required to maintain uniform motion, force was<br />

only required to change the state of motion. The change in the concept of inertia which Newton<br />

later formulated more precisely probably constitutes the most important element in the transition<br />

from antique and mediaeval science to classical science. It is one of the foundations which<br />

underlie the most essential parts of the new world-view, and it is beyond dispute that this change<br />

was largely brought about by Galileo. When he is talking about the phenomena of inertia,<br />

Galileo often, however, more-or-less lapses into the modes of expression and thought employed<br />

by the Scholastics of the 1300s and also by modern schoolchildren: everything that moves is<br />

moved by something else. This should not be a surprise, because Copernicus, Kepler and Galileo<br />

continued to view the universe as a sphere with a finite radius, even if they believed that radius<br />

to be much large than their predecessors had done. 190<br />

Galileo, like Kepler made a clear distinction between the world which is absolute, objective,<br />

immutable and mathematical, and that which is relative, subjective, fluctuating and sensible.<br />

189 Dijksterhuis 1986, 380. Tarnas 1998, 264. Burtt 1980, 73-5. Galileo’s speculations about inertia, relativity and<br />

the composition of motions were largely directed at refuting the physical objections that had previously been raised<br />

to the idea that the earth was in motion. Using his new concept of inertia, Galileo was able, for example, to explain<br />

why a body thrown vertically upwards into the air fell back on its starting position even though the earth was<br />

moving. It was indeed moving - like all other things on earth - forwards at the same velocity as the earth. This<br />

common motion of all things could not however be observed via any experiments carried out on the earth.<br />

77

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!