27.02.2014 Views

Understanding global security - Peter Hough

Understanding global security - Peter Hough

Understanding global security - Peter Hough

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

SOCIAL IDENTITY AS A THREAT TO SECURITY<br />

repressive policies in the name of ‘nation building’. Women, the disabled, homosexuals<br />

and people linked by any other form of collective identity stand little chance<br />

of having their ‘cultural differences’ respected when they overlap with far more<br />

influential ‘cultures’. Entrusting states to be the arbiters of human rights frequently<br />

leads to the imposition of dominant cultural norms on minority cultures in precisely<br />

the fashion that relativism purports to prevent. Rhoda Howard has referred to this<br />

as ‘cultural absolutism’, as a counter to the relativist claim that human rights are a<br />

form of absolutism (Howard 1995).<br />

Even if a more optimistic view of the relationship between states and individuals<br />

than that encouraged by recent history is taken, they still offer a limited guarantee<br />

of future human <strong>security</strong> since their own position is far from secure. The life span of<br />

many states over the last century has been much the same as that of their citizens.<br />

The economic rights afforded to its people by the USSR and its allies, such as<br />

employment, disappeared with the fall of Communism as quickly as the civil and<br />

political rights of Latvians, Estonians and Lithuanians had been snuffed out by their<br />

annexation by the USSR.<br />

It can further be argued that relativism in regard to ethics and rights is not only<br />

unhelpful but ontologically flawed. The temptation to want to protect the weak from<br />

the strong in international affairs is obvious but think for a moment about the<br />

implications of applying cultural relativism in other situations. If cultural relativism<br />

should apply at the <strong>global</strong> level, should it not also be applied at the domestic level<br />

to recognize the impunity of criminal culture from the imposition of state values? If<br />

it is wrong to universally apply values then why is it not wrong to universally apply<br />

cultural relativism? If all cultural moralities are equally valid does this mean that<br />

contradictory moral opinions can each be valid?<br />

The (strong) relativists’ answer to the final of these three questions is to adopt<br />

the position of ‘methodological relativism’ or ‘truth relativism’ and suggest that the<br />

idea of validity has no bearing in ethics, or indeed in any social scientific context.<br />

This position, associated in Sociology with Bloor (1976) and in Philosophy with<br />

Davson-Galle (1998), posits that moral judgements have no rational basis and are,<br />

in effect, no more than matters of taste. This position, however, can lead only to a<br />

nihilistic abandonment of reason and the tolerance of intolerance. Abandoning reason<br />

and any notion of right and wrong in ethics is not only unhelpful in terms of giving<br />

the green light to genocide and any other form of human abuse, it can also be argued<br />

to be logically flawed. Proving truths in a social context is more difficult than in<br />

natural science but some philosophical methods have been advanced to show that<br />

moral judgements can be rationalized. Apel, for example, demonstrates that people<br />

necessarily accept certain fundamental ethical norms as binding in the process<br />

of making everyday communication possible. In any form of communication the<br />

idea of truth and lies must implicitly be accepted by someone communicating or<br />

communication would have no meaning. Even habitual liars could not consistently<br />

lie to themselves (Apel 1990). The strict observance of truth relativism would mean<br />

that you could not participate in any discussion on ethics. Those philosophers,<br />

anthropologists and others who deny the universality of rights do so by making<br />

arguments grounded in reason. Zemin in upholding the relativity of human rights on<br />

his 1996 visit to the USA did so by justifying China’s different interpretation of the<br />

concept to that favoured in the West. In a world in which transnational communication<br />

130

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!