14.06.2013 Views

1 The Birth of Science - MSRI

1 The Birth of Science - MSRI

1 The Birth of Science - MSRI

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

6.4 Definitions, Scientific Terms and <strong>The</strong>oretical Entities 157<br />

the notion in Aristotle were <strong>of</strong> this type. 32 Euclid avoids the word <br />

in the Elements, using instead ¨, which originally meant “sign”. 33<br />

This replacement suggests that Euclid may have wished to cut himself<br />

<strong>of</strong>f from the tradition <strong>of</strong> Platonic speculations on the true nature <strong>of</strong> the<br />

point, sticking to a conventionalist notion <strong>of</strong> language and a new notion <strong>of</strong><br />

mathematics. This new way <strong>of</strong> seeing mathematical entities is in evidence page 202<br />

in some <strong>of</strong> Euclid’s definitions, in particular the definition <strong>of</strong> proportion.<br />

If one thinks <strong>of</strong> the “ratio between magnitudes” as something that exists<br />

in and <strong>of</strong> itself, the equality <strong>of</strong> two ratios seems like an obvious notion (as<br />

it did to Galileo 34 ), whereas Euclid’s definition, as we saw in Section 2.5,<br />

is tantamount to a subtle and complex implicit definition <strong>of</strong> the notion <strong>of</strong><br />

the ratio between magnitudes.<br />

Nominalist definitions are certainly very valuable for enriching scientific<br />

terminology, but they cannot create it from scratch. Any definition <strong>of</strong><br />

this type can only reduce the meaning <strong>of</strong> a new term to that <strong>of</strong> terms already<br />

assumed known. Just as the hypothetico-deductive method requires<br />

demonstrationless statements on which to build, so the nominalist definition<br />

procedure requires definitionless terms from which to start.<br />

<strong>The</strong> awareness <strong>of</strong> the need to avoid infinite regress, which must be clear<br />

to a person who shares a nominalist view <strong>of</strong> definitions, is documented<br />

already in pre-Hellenistic philosophy. Thus, Aristotle reports that, according<br />

to the school <strong>of</strong> Antisthenes, since every definition requires a reference<br />

to something else, it is only possible to define what is composite (whether<br />

materially or conceptually), not what is simple. 35 This observation <strong>of</strong> Antisthenes<br />

is not an isolated one, because around 200 A.D. Sextus Empiricus<br />

wrote:<br />

And given that, if we want to define everything we define nothing at<br />

all, because <strong>of</strong> regression to infinity, whereas if we admit that some<br />

things can be understood without definition we are declaring that<br />

definitions are not necessary for understanding, . . . we must either<br />

define nothing at all or declare that definitions are not necessary. 36<br />

<strong>The</strong> conclusion drawn by Sextus Empiricus reflects his own Skeptic<br />

ideas. What concerns us is that the possibility <strong>of</strong> “admitting that some<br />

32 Sample passages are listed in note 228 on page 287; see also the surrounding discussion.<br />

33 <strong>The</strong> occasional presence in some works <strong>of</strong> the Aristotelian corpus <strong>of</strong> this word ¨ in the<br />

sense <strong>of</strong> “point” is neither here nor there, because these works were certainly revised in post-<br />

Euclidean times. <strong>The</strong> term recurs, for example, in some geometric constructions contained in the<br />

Meteorologica (see especially 373a and 375b–377a), whose redaction into the form that has come<br />

down to us is probably due to a student <strong>of</strong> <strong>The</strong>ophrastus.<br />

34 We will return to this on page 307.<br />

35 Aristotle, Metaphysica, VIII, 3, 1043b, 23–32.<br />

36 Sextus Empiricus, Pyrrhoneae hypotyposes, II, xvi, 207–208.<br />

Revision: 1.7 Date: 2002/09/14 23:17:37

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!