14.06.2013 Views

1 The Birth of Science - MSRI

1 The Birth of Science - MSRI

1 The Birth of Science - MSRI

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

7.4 Propositional Logic 191<br />

Regarding the dream <strong>of</strong> incest between son and mother, Artemidorus<br />

talks as if he knew <strong>of</strong> and agreed with Freud’s ideas about<br />

the Oedipus complex. 49<br />

7.4 Propositional Logic<br />

Aristotle devoted much attention to logic, and syllogisms in particular.<br />

But in his analysis <strong>of</strong> the various forms <strong>of</strong> syllogisms their validity was<br />

justified only through the evidence provided by examples. In other words,<br />

he described the use <strong>of</strong> logic, but he did not formulate a theory there<strong>of</strong>, in<br />

our sense <strong>of</strong> the word.<br />

<strong>The</strong> first steps toward a scientific theory <strong>of</strong> logic seem to have been taken<br />

around 300 B.C. by Diodorus Cronus and Philo the Dialectician. <strong>The</strong> latter<br />

is known to have defined the conditional proposition “if p then q” as<br />

“not (p and not q)”. 50 But although his awareness <strong>of</strong> the need for a crisp,<br />

unambiguous definition <strong>of</strong> the conditional seems to herald pro<strong>of</strong>s <strong>of</strong> theo- page 242<br />

rems in logic, on the whole the existing testimonia point to Chrysippus as<br />

the founder <strong>of</strong> the scientific theory <strong>of</strong> propositional logic. While Aristotle<br />

adopted variables to represent generic terms in propositions, Chrysippus<br />

used them to stand for the propositions themselves, and constructed a<br />

theory <strong>of</strong> logical inference based on five postulates. 51 If we use p and q to<br />

denote generic propositions, the five inference rules assumed by Chrysippus<br />

as undemonstrated correspond to the five lines below; the first two entries<br />

<strong>of</strong> each line are premises and the last says what can be deduced from<br />

them.<br />

1. if p then q p q<br />

2. if p then q not q not p<br />

3. not (p and q) p not q<br />

4. p or 52 q p not q<br />

5. p or 52 q not p q<br />

From these five postulates an unlimited number <strong>of</strong> inference schemes<br />

could be deduced as theorems. But none <strong>of</strong> Chrysippus’ theorems in logic<br />

has been preserved.<br />

49 [Artemidorus/Musatti], p. 17.<br />

50 Sextus Empiricus, Adversus dogmaticos, II, 113; Pyrrhoneae hypotyposes, II, xi, 110.<br />

51 <strong>The</strong>se five postulates are listed by Diogenes Laertius (Vitae philosophorum, VII, 79–81) and by<br />

Sextus Empiricus (Pyrrhoneae hypotyposes, II, xiii, 157–158). Another passage <strong>of</strong> Sextus (Adversus<br />

dogmaticos, II, 224–227) reports only the first three postulates but gives more information about<br />

theorems in logic.<br />

52 Here “or” is understood in the exclusive sense: either p or q is true but not both.<br />

Revision: 1.9 Date: 2002/10/11 23:59:33

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!