27.06.2013 Views

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

THE 'PROJET' OF 1672 139<br />

Lectiones XVIII treated optics as the mathematical science aimed at the<br />

analysis of the behavior of light rays. Priority was with the laws of optics,<br />

being laws of rays that were justified empirically <strong>and</strong> generally accepted. In<br />

this sense the lectures stood with both feet in traditional geometrical optics.<br />

Yet, Barrow was too conscious of epistemic issues regarding mathematics<br />

<strong>and</strong> of the new developments in natural philosophy to treat optics in the<br />

outright traditional manner of other contemporary works. A good example is<br />

the Opera mathematica, a mathematics textbook from 1669 by the Flemish<br />

Jesuit Andreas Tacquet, a correspondent of Huygens. In its catoptrical<br />

chapters, Tacquet makes room for a noncommittal survey of explanations of<br />

reflection: some give natural economy as the ‘ratio’ of reflection, others<br />

maintain that the perpendicular component of a ray’s motion is inverted, <strong>and</strong><br />

so on. 116 Even Descartes is reviewed, stripped of all corpuscular trimmings to<br />

be sure. Tacquet did not show preference for any of the alternatives, he only<br />

explained the various ways in which the law of reflection could be deduced.<br />

The business of a mathematical student of light was to establish those<br />

properties of rays interacting with varying mediums so that the laws<br />

describing its behavior could be derived logically.<br />

For Barrow mixed mathematics - where natural things are considered in<br />

their quantitative aspects - was a genuine part of mathematics. In his lectures<br />

on mathematics, Barrow effectively discarded the distinction between<br />

sensible <strong>and</strong> intelligible matter, so that a science like optics could approach<br />

the certainty of geometry. The certainty of inferences only depended on the<br />

certainty of the presuppositions - axioms, postulates, principles. 117 Barrow<br />

presented his explanations as a non-committal elucidation of empirically<br />

founded laws, similar to the mechanical analogies of perspectivist theory.<br />

The new mode of thought regarding the nature of things had changed the<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the nature of light <strong>and</strong> the causes of reflection <strong>and</strong><br />

refraction. Yet, compared to these, corpuscular accounts of the causes of<br />

reflection <strong>and</strong> refraction obtained a different meaning, as it implied a<br />

potential claim about the true nature of light. This, combined with his<br />

epistemic awareness, may explain Barrow’s reluctance to make strong claims<br />

about his explanations.<br />

In his comments, Barrow considerably qualified the status of his theory<br />

of light <strong>and</strong> his causal accounts. His focus was on the laws <strong>and</strong> he did not<br />

elaborate his account of the mechanistic nature of light in any detail or<br />

explore its consequences. He was rather vague about the necessity <strong>and</strong> role<br />

of such an account. The laws of optics should ‘not be repugnant to reason’<br />

<strong>and</strong> be given ‘some support of reason’. He invoked a law of motion, but did<br />

not intend to prove the laws like Descartes, by deriving them from his theory<br />

of light. He offered a physical rationale for the laws, without making clear<br />

the exact purpose of his explanations. As a consequence, he parried the<br />

116<br />

Tacquet, Opera mathematica (Antwerp, 1669), Catoptricae libri tres, 217-218<br />

117<br />

Shapiro, Fits, 31-36.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!