27.06.2013 Views

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

LENSES & WAVES 261<br />

other part of physical optics in which experiment was used as a heuristic tool<br />

for exploring new phenomena of light <strong>and</strong> establishing their mathematical<br />

properties. In this way he had extended the mathematical science of optics to<br />

the quality of color. Huygens had extended it to the mechanistic causes of<br />

the laws of optics. By applying Galileo’s science of motion to the motions of<br />

ethereal particles, he had invented the most complete form of mathematical<br />

physics in the seventeenth century.<br />

Huygens <strong>and</strong> Descartes<br />

Traité de la Lumière gave a new form to mechanistic science, the first<br />

‘thoroughly Cartesian’ theory of light. Yet – <strong>and</strong> this is the gist of my<br />

argument – it was not the outcome of some program in mechanistic, or even<br />

Cartesian, science. A careful reconstruction of what exactly were the leading<br />

questions for Huygens, juxtaposed with comparable pursuits of other<br />

protagonists of seventeenth-century optics, reveals that Huygens’ wave<br />

theory was the outcome of his typically rigorous <strong>and</strong> tenacious approach to a<br />

problem raised in the context of geometrical optics. As was his wont, he first<br />

of all wanted to get the mathematics of his solution right. He wanted the<br />

explanations of the various laws to be mathematical derivations that were<br />

mutually consistent. As a result of the particular character of the ‘matter’ of<br />

geometrical optics – light rays, which had come to be seen as being of a<br />

mechanistic nature – he got involved in mechanistic questions. He did so in a<br />

deliberately mathematical way, intending to stick to the rigor of mathematics<br />

he missed in the reasonings of his fellows at the Académie. He believed in<br />

the power of mathematical reasoning <strong>and</strong> did not content himself with illdefined<br />

mechanisms.<br />

This reaction to the Parisian Cartesians can be seen as a continuation of<br />

what I regard as Huygens’ lifelong reaction to Descartes. Much of his oeuvre<br />

was a direct response to what Descartes had said on impact, circular motion,<br />

curves, lenses, light, halos, etc. He did so in a clearly mechanistic context,<br />

accepting fundamental concepts <strong>and</strong> drawing inspiration from some of<br />

Descartes’ ideas. In his theories of gravity <strong>and</strong> light he also considered the<br />

conceptualization of the mechanistic nature of things. Discours was induced<br />

by the – in his view – obscurities vented on the Parisian scene. Pardies may<br />

have inspired his thinking on the nature of light <strong>and</strong> the intellectual climate<br />

at the Académie, but strange refraction – together with the problem of<br />

caustics – may well have been the sole occasion for Huygens’ consideration<br />

of the mechanics of light propagation.<br />

As an adolescent, Huygens had soaked up Principia Philosophiae <strong>and</strong> its<br />

clarity of reasoning had made an indelible impression on him. The idea that<br />

nature ultimately consists of passive matter in motion was always at the back<br />

of his mind. But this does not turn Huygens into a Cartesian. Mechanistic<br />

philosophy was merely a tacitly assumed background of his thinking.<br />

Huygens quite consistently confined himself to the mathematics of these

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!