27.06.2013 Views

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

154 CHAPTER 4<br />

left aside the possible physical implications of his Cartesian analysis of<br />

strange refraction. It remains to be seen how seriously he took his proposal.<br />

In view of his commitment to a wave conception one might say that<br />

Huygens was just taking considerable liberty of reasoning in order to see<br />

how far he could get at fathoming the oddities of strange refraction.<br />

Huygens also afforded himself liberty in another respect. In his notes, he<br />

did not explain his motives for proposing an alternative to Bartholinus’ law.<br />

Like Bartholinus, he extended the mathematical structure of the sine law<br />

through rational analysis. He did not question Bartholinus’ data <strong>and</strong> confined<br />

his study to mathematical analysis. 152 Also, irrespective of the virtues of<br />

Bartholinus’ verification, Huygens made no effort to justify his conclusions<br />

empirically. If his alternative was more general, he did not check whether it<br />

was anywhere near the truth. Huygens was familiar with such an approach of<br />

mathematical reasoning <strong>and</strong> it had been successful several times. Although in<br />

his optical studies in De Aberratione it had led him somewhat astray, in his<br />

studies of motion this strategy had been very rewarding. As mentioned in<br />

chapter three, an empirical study of gravitational acceleration had got him<br />

nowhere. The breakthrough had been effected by mathematical analysis of<br />

circular motion.<br />

In his correction of Descartes’ rules of impact, Huygens likewise relied on<br />

rational analysis. He built upon the established, Galilean laws of motion to<br />

find the true laws of impact by means of rational analysis, a strategy he also<br />

chose in his analysis of strange refraction where he built upon the established<br />

law of ordinary refraction. Huygens carried out his study of impact between<br />

1652 <strong>and</strong> 1656. It has been discussed in full detail by Westfall. 153 He had<br />

found out that Descartes’ rules of impact - a crucial topic in mechanistic<br />

philosophy - where wrong save for the first. In particular in the case of<br />

unequal bodies or speeds, the rules proved inconsistent <strong>and</strong> failed to obey<br />

Galileo’s principle of relativity. Huygens’ solution lay in rigorously applying<br />

this principle, in combination with the principle of inertia. In so doing, he<br />

converted the study of impact into an extension of Galileo’s theory of<br />

uniform motion, namely, the inertial motion of the center of gravity of two<br />

colliding bodies. 154 As Westfall shows elaborately, the main thread in<br />

Huygens’ study of impact was an increasing desire to treat impact in terms of<br />

velocities instead of forces, which in his view defied mathematical clarity. As<br />

we shall see in the next chapter, the concept of velocity would be crucial to<br />

Huygens’ underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the mechanistic causes of natural phenomena. In<br />

his study of impact Huygens repeatedly solved problems by transforming<br />

them into problems subject to known principles. The principle of relativity<br />

made possible the treatment of all collisions of equal bodies. Collisions of<br />

152 There is no way Ziggelaar’s observation that “Huygens repeats carefully the experiments of Bartholin<br />

on the crystal, measures more exactly, …” can be substantiated. Ziggelaar, “How”, 182.<br />

153 Westfall, Force, 149-155.<br />

154 Westfall, Force, 152-153.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!