27.06.2013 Views

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

1653 - TRACTATUS 33<br />

focused on problems pertaining to their configurations in actual telescopes.<br />

Like Kepler, Huygens intended to found the dioptrical properties on a sound<br />

mathematical basis. Whether a continuation of Dioptrice was his actual goal,<br />

can only be surmised as he did not explicitly refer to it in such a<br />

programmatic sense. Huygens did know Dioptrice, it had been on the reading<br />

list of his mathematics tutor Stampioen <strong>and</strong> much later he commended it to<br />

his brother Constantijn as the best introduction to dioptrics. 80 Huygens did<br />

not have much to offer that was not already known. Tractatus covered more<br />

types of lenses but the eventual results regarding the focal distances of lenses<br />

<strong>and</strong> the magnifying properties did not differ much from Dioptrice. The crucial<br />

difference is that Huygens founded his results on a general <strong>and</strong> exact theory<br />

of focal distances. It rigorously proved Kepler’s results. He had the exact law<br />

of refraction at his disposal <strong>and</strong> thus could be exact where Kepler necessarily<br />

had to leave his readers with approximate answers.<br />

Perspectiva <strong>and</strong> the telescope<br />

At the same time when Kepler wrote Dioptrice, two other scholars devised an<br />

account of the telescope. Della Porta’s ‘De telescopio’ remained<br />

unpublished, De Domini’s De Radiis Visus et Lucis was published in 1611.<br />

Both were based on perspectivist theory of image formation. Before I go on<br />

to discuss the impact of the sine law on dioptrics, I briefly discuss these in<br />

order to make it clear why that perspectivist theory was intrinsically<br />

inadequate to account fully for the effect of lenses.<br />

Shortly before his death, Della Porta extended his theory of lenses of De<br />

Refractione to telescopes in a manuscript ‘De telescopio’. 81 It reveals the<br />

problems lenses posed for perspectivist theory of image formation. In order<br />

to determine the place where an object is seen, perspectiva used the cathetus<br />

rule. The cathetus is the line through the object point, perpendicular to the<br />

reflecting or refracting surface. The cathetus rule states that the image is the<br />

intersection of the ray entering the eye <strong>and</strong> the cathetus. Modern Keplerian<br />

theory shows that, although valid in many cases, this rule turns out to break<br />

down for curved surfaces in particular. To account for images of lenses<br />

another problem turns up. As a lens refracts a ray twice, this seems to imply<br />

that the rule has to be applied twice also. Della Porta avoided this problem<br />

by considering only one cathetus.<br />

Della Porta considered a lens in terms of refracting spheres, as he had<br />

done in De Refractione (Figure 17). The dotted lines indicate such spheres <strong>and</strong><br />

the lens dcgf is formed by their overlap. 82 The object ab is perceived as<br />

follows: a ray from point a is refracted along cd to the eye. Della Porta drew<br />

the cathetus ka of the lower surface of the lens, which also is its radius.<br />

When produced, the ray entering the eye intersects the cathetus in point h,<br />

80<br />

OC1, 6 (Stampioen’s list of recommended readings spans pages 5-10) <strong>and</strong> OC6, 215.<br />

81<br />

Della Porta’s account of refraction by spheres <strong>and</strong> lenses in De refractione is discussed in Lindberg,<br />

“Optics in 16th century Italy”, 143-146.<br />

82<br />

Della Porta, De Telescopio, 113-114.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!