27.06.2013 Views

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

200 CHAPTER 5<br />

mathematical. 125 It assumed a constant difference between the parallel<br />

components of the colored rays. The law can be seen as a natural extension<br />

to dispersion of Descartes’ derivation of the sine law, identifying the variety<br />

of colors with various sizes of the parallel component. 126<br />

In Opticks this ‘Cartesian’ dispersion law has disappeared. Supposedly,<br />

Newton had realized that his dispersion law implied that color depended<br />

upon velocity. This he could not accept, as the immutability of colors was<br />

the core of his theory. As velocity changes in even the most elementary<br />

mechanisms, it seemed a unlikely c<strong>and</strong>idate for an original <strong>and</strong> conservable<br />

property of light rays. 127 Therefore, the ‘Cartesian’ dispersion law of the<br />

optical lectures was unacceptable. 128 This left a model for dispersion based on<br />

size or mass, but Newton never articulated a mechanism through which<br />

different refrangibility might be explained this way. What is more, the only<br />

mechanism he elaborated for refraction – based on perpendicular forces<br />

acting upon particles – was at odds with such a model, for acceleration is<br />

independent of mass. In Opticks, Newton put forward an alternative law of<br />

dispersion with dubious empirical evidence <strong>and</strong> whose mechanistic causes he<br />

had never elaborated – not even in private. 129<br />

The status of ‘raisons de mechanique’<br />

In the seclusion of his private quarters, Newton allowed himself a far greater<br />

liberty of reasoning than in his publications. From the very start, his<br />

experimental inquiries had been accompanied by speculations on the<br />

corpuscular nature of light <strong>and</strong> colors. Shapiro has analyzed the way in which<br />

Newton employed his vibration model to develop his theory of periodicity of<br />

colors. 130 The derivation of the sine law shows that Newton was on a par<br />

with Huygens as regards the mathematization of mechanistic causes. He<br />

employed the method of transduction with a comparable meticulousness<br />

mathematizing the physics of unobservable particles by founding them upon<br />

the established laws of motion. Unfortunately, Newton’s consideration of<br />

‘raison de mechanique’ turned problematic because it produced discrepancies<br />

that left considerable gaps in his mathematical science of colors. It did not<br />

affect his experimental theory of color, though. Although he did not have an<br />

exact law of dispersion, the experimentally disclosed <strong>and</strong> secured theory of<br />

different refrangibility stood unshaken.<br />

125 Newton, Optical papers 1, 199 & 335-337.<br />

126 See Shapiro, “Dispersion law”, 99-104 & 126-127; Bechler, “Newton’s search”, 4-5. I discuss this<br />

matter in more detail in my “Once Snel breaks down”.<br />

127 Bechler, “Newton’s search”, 32-33.<br />

128 In 1691, Newton figured out a test for the assumption that color differs with velocity: when a moon of<br />

Jupiter disappears behind the planet the slowest color – red – should be seen last. In February 1692,<br />

Flamsteed reported that such a difference could not be observed. This empirical evidence definitely ruled<br />

out velocity. Shapiro, Fits, 144-146.<br />

129 Newton, Opticks, 128-130. Shapiro, “Dispersion law”, 97-99; 126-127. Shapiro suggests that it might be<br />

based upon a small angle approximation of refracting angles.<br />

130 Shapiro, Fits, 200-201.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!