27.06.2013 Views

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

256 CHAPTER 7<br />

Huygens was the first (<strong>and</strong> for a long time the only one) to pursue the<br />

question raised by Kepler right after the invention of the telescope: how can<br />

we underst<strong>and</strong> its working in a mathematical way? Students of dioptrics like<br />

Descartes, Barrow, <strong>and</strong> Newton focused on solving sophisticated<br />

mathematical problems like determining aplanatic surfaces <strong>and</strong> analyzing<br />

optical imagery. They did not elaborate their findings to explain the<br />

dioptrical properties of ordinary lenses <strong>and</strong> their configurations.<br />

Astronomical observers, starting with Galileo, did not elaborate a dioptrical<br />

theory of telescopes either. Only when the telescope was turned, towards<br />

1670, into an instrument of precision did its users like Flamsteed <strong>and</strong> Picard<br />

begin to bother about questions of dioptrics. Without Huygens’<br />

mathematical proficiency they could not, however, obtain the rigor <strong>and</strong><br />

generality of Tractatus <strong>and</strong> De Aberratione. But Huygens was not of help, he<br />

never came to publish his dioptrics.<br />

Despite the fact that he always had an open eye for practical implications,<br />

the orientation on instruments characteristic of Dioptrica cannot be directly<br />

generalized. The organ did not direct his studies of consonance, as clocks did<br />

not direct his studies of motion. 1 Still, in a broader sense Dioptrica does reveal<br />

a particular feature of Huygens’ science. Whereas Descartes contented<br />

himself with establishing the principles of refraction <strong>and</strong> perfect vision,<br />

Huygens applied the sine law to establish the properties of actual lenses <strong>and</strong><br />

telescopes. Whereas others analyzed the mathematics of lenses in order to<br />

find perfectly focusing surfaces, he did so in order to underst<strong>and</strong> the<br />

properties of real lenses <strong>and</strong> fathom their imperfections mathematically.<br />

What Huygens did in Dioptrica – apart from the practical relevance of his<br />

pursuits – was elaborating mathematical theory by applying general principles<br />

to specific problems of real objects.<br />

Huygens ‘applied geometry to matter’, to use his phrase in Traité de la<br />

Lumière. Real, rather than ideal matter. Application in the sense of elaborating<br />

established mathematical theory for particular cases, rather than<br />

mathematization of new phenomena in the sense Newton did with colors.<br />

Even in his theories of impact <strong>and</strong> circular motion he substantially built<br />

upon mathematical foundations already laid by Galileo. As contrasted to<br />

Newton, he mathematized no phenomena that had not already latently been<br />

mathematized. Rather than establishing an investigation into the physics of<br />

consonance, he elaborated the mathematics of the coincidence theory. In<br />

dioptrics, he confined himself to the analysis of the properties of refracted<br />

rays <strong>and</strong> left colors for what they were. Brilliantly pursuing mathematical<br />

reasoning, he rarely went beyond the established boundaries of the<br />

mathematical sciences.<br />

One cannot escape the impression that the elaboration of mathematical<br />

theory for particular problems interested him more than laying new<br />

1<br />

Although these have never, to my knowledge, been studied from the viewpoint of the relationship<br />

between theory <strong>and</strong> practice.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!