27.06.2013 Views

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

Lenses and Waves

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

50 CHAPTER 2<br />

most part derived from Huygens’ dioptrical theories, <strong>and</strong> I will not discuss<br />

them in further detail. 164<br />

Huygens’ position<br />

Picard’s dioptrical fragments bring us back to Huygens. What had he been<br />

doing in the meantime? In Systema saturnium he had alluded to an elaborate<br />

theory of dioptrics, which we know he possessed indeed. Yet, despite<br />

ongoing requests to publish it, he had kept it to himself. It may be clear by<br />

now that Tractatus is a unique work in the development of seventeenthcentury<br />

dioptrics. Huygens was the first <strong>and</strong> only man to follow the lead of<br />

Dioptrice. Like Kepler, he combined the two things necessary to develop a<br />

theory of the telescope: mathematical proficiency <strong>and</strong> an orientation on the<br />

instrument. Unlike Kepler, he had the exact law of refraction <strong>and</strong> thus he<br />

could rigorously develop an exact theory of the telescope.<br />

But did Huygens really follow Kepler? Did he want to underst<strong>and</strong> the<br />

telescope in view of its use in astronomy? Tractatus came into being well<br />

before Huygens commenced his practical activities of telescope making <strong>and</strong><br />

astronomical observation (discussed in the next chapter). Unlike Flamsteed<br />

<strong>and</strong> Picard, he did not seek answers to questions that had arisen in practice.<br />

Nevertheless, his orientation on the telescope is clear. He passed by all those<br />

sophisticated problems not relevant to the underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the telescope<br />

that preoccupied mathematicians like Barrow. However, nowhere does<br />

Huygens mention Kepler as an example. It looks as if developing a theory of<br />

the telescope on the basis of the sine law was to him an interesting<br />

mathematical puzzle, maybe just to correct Descartes’ useless approach to<br />

dioptrics. The problem had not yet been solved <strong>and</strong> Huygens only too gladly<br />

seized the opportunity. Which makes his exclusive orientation on the<br />

instrument all the more interesting.<br />

The transformation of the telescope into an instrument of precision<br />

brought back an interest in the dioptrical properties of the telescope. In this<br />

regard, one might say that Kepler had prematurely raised the question after a<br />

mathematical underst<strong>and</strong>ing of the telescope. In 1611, it was a qualitative<br />

instrument <strong>and</strong> remained so for another half century. To underst<strong>and</strong> its<br />

working, a qualitative account of the effects of lenses therefore sufficed.<br />

Similarly, we can ask whether an exact theory like Huygens’ was really<br />

needed. It seems that Kepler’s or Keplerian theories satisfied the needs of<br />

men like Flamsteed <strong>and</strong> Molyneux pretty well. They lacked sufficient<br />

proficiency in mathematics to treat lenses in exact terms, but they may also<br />

have been perfectly satisfied with their approximate results.<br />

Huygens himself did not put much work in applying his theory to the<br />

questions that occupied Picard <strong>and</strong> Flamsteed. The principle of the<br />

micrometer may or may not have been the result of his theoretical<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing, in Systema saturnium he explained it only briefly. Huygens did<br />

164 Blay, “Travaux de Picard”, 340.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!