04.10.2015 Views

ECONOMY

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

884 anarchy<br />

one in which f (G i )=G m i<br />

,wherem > 0 (and often, for technical reasons, 1 ≥ m),<br />

so that:<br />

G m 1<br />

p 1 (G 1 , G 2 )=<br />

G m 1 + G m 2<br />

For this form the probability of winning depends on the ratio of guns expenditures<br />

by the two parties. Some effects of different military technologies can be captured by<br />

the parameter m; for example, the technology of seventeenth-century warfare during<br />

the Thirty Years War, with its large armies and artillery units, can be thought of as<br />

having a higher value for this parameter than the feudal levies of medieval Europe.<br />

Such factors have consequences for the size of political units.<br />

(4)<br />

1.2 How Power is Determined<br />

We can now examine how the two countries can be expected to distribute their<br />

resources between guns and butter in this simple setting. We abstract away from<br />

all the collective action problems as well as those of strategic interaction between<br />

domestic political groups, and suppose that each country behaves as a unitary actor.<br />

With both countries caring about how much butter they will consume and supposing<br />

that they are risk neutral, 3 the expected payoffs intheeventofwar,inwhichthe<br />

winner receives all the butter and the loser receives nothing, would be the following:<br />

W 1 (G 1 , G 2 )= p 1 (G 1 , G 2 )(B 1 + B 2 )= p 1 (G 1 , G 2 )[‚ 1 (R 1 −G 1 )+‚ 2 (R 2 −G 2 )]<br />

W 2 (G 1 ,G 2 )= p 2 (G 1 ,G 2 )(B 1 + B 2 )= p 2 (G 1 , G 2 )[‚ 1 (R 1 −G 1 )+‚ 2 (R 2 −G 2 )] (5)<br />

Note that these two payoffs are thought of as depending on the expenditures on<br />

guns by the two parties, since given (2) the choice of guns by each party determines<br />

the quantity of butter as well. Furthermore, because these payoffs arederivedonthe<br />

condition that the two countries are risk neutral, the probability of winning for each<br />

country, p 1 (G 1 , G 2 )andp 2 (G 1 , G 2 ), can also be interpreted as the share of total<br />

butter each country receives in the shadow of war.<br />

We are interested in deriving Nash equilibrium strategies for guns—that is, a<br />

combination (G ∗ 1 , G ∗ 2 ) such that W 1(G ∗ 1 , G ∗ 2 ) ≥ W 1(G 1 , G ∗ 2 ) for all G 1 and<br />

W 2 (G ∗ 1 , G ∗ 2 ) ≥ W 2(G ∗ 1 , G 2) for all G 2 . At a Nash equilibrium there is no incentive<br />

for any party to deviate in their strategies. At that equilibrium the marginal benefit of<br />

each country’s choice of guns equals its marginal cost so that:<br />

∂p 1 (G ∗ 1 , G ∗ 2 )<br />

∂G 1<br />

(B ∗ 1 + B ∗ 2 )= p 1(G ∗ 1 , G ∗ 2 )‚ 1<br />

∂p 2 (G ∗ 1 , G ∗ 2 )<br />

∂G 2<br />

(B ∗ 1 + B ∗ 2 )= p 2(G ∗ 1 , G ∗ 2 )‚ 2 (6)<br />

³ Under risk neutrality there is neither aversion towards risk nor love of risk. Clearly, this is a strong<br />

assumption that is nevertheless analytically very convenient that is almost always adopted when a certain<br />

problem is first modeled. We discuss the effects of risk aversion in Section 2.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!