04.10.2015 Views

ECONOMY

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

arry r. weingast & donald a. wittman 15<br />

positions but not about their relative quality. Again, the voters are rational and the<br />

pressure group has private information (in this case, about the relative quality of<br />

the candidates). A number of recent papers consider this case but employ differing<br />

subsidiary assumptions: advertising has content (see Coate 2004; Wittman forthcoming);<br />

advertising has no content, but expenditures on advertising signal information<br />

(Prat 2002, this volume); pressure groups make the offers (Coate, Prat),<br />

candidates make the offers; there is one pressure group, there are multiple pressure<br />

groups; the candidates are only interested in winning, and the candidates have policy<br />

goals. These various modeling efforts do not all come to the same positive conclusion<br />

as the previous paragraph. In general, the results depend on whether the value of<br />

the revealed information is outweighed by the loss from inferior candidate positions<br />

when the candidates compete for pressure group funds. In turn, this balance depends<br />

to a great degree on the number of pressure groups and whether it is the candidates or<br />

the pressure groups that make the offer. All these various modeling efforts take into<br />

account that information valuable to uniformed voters is revealed by the pressure<br />

group’s donation or endorsement and all of them assume rationality of the voters.<br />

This is the key methodological advance—how voters can incorporate information<br />

that others might want to distort or hide (see Prat, this volume).<br />

We have shown how uninformed voters can make inferences from behavior and<br />

thereby become more informed. Because all of this is embedded in a game, all<br />

other players take this behavior and information into account when they make their<br />

decisions; and of course the uninformed take the other players’ strategies into account<br />

when they make their own inferences. 15<br />

The final example for this section considers aggregation of information in the<br />

context of voting. Suppose a set of voters face a decision about how much money<br />

to spend. To gain intuition, we begin with an exceedingly simple example. Suppose<br />

that there are five voters with identical preferences: three have unbiased estimates of<br />

the correct action to take, while two are fully informed. The voters know whether they<br />

are informed or not. The uninformed know that there are informed voters, but not<br />

how many. Suppose further that the correct action is to spend $7 million and that,<br />

with equal probability, the uninformed players receive a signal that it should be 5, 7,<br />

or 9 million dollars. Assuming that the voters cannot communicate with each other,<br />

howlikelyisitthatthemajorityruledecisionisnot7? The answer is zero if the voters<br />

are rational: all the uninformed voters will rationally abstain. By doing so, they know<br />

that only informed voters will participate and that these informed voters will make<br />

the correct decision.<br />

This example illustrates two important but related issues. First, the more informed<br />

people will choose to vote (here, at least, the argument does not go against conventional<br />

wisdom). Second, the potential voter asks: given that he will be pivotal, should<br />

¹⁵ There are other ways in which voters can be informed despite an apparent lack of information.<br />

Parties create brand names so that party labels are in fact informative about a candidate’s position (Cox<br />

and McCubbins 1993, 2005). Relying on biased information can be rational for voters who have strong<br />

priors in favor of one of the parties (Calvert 1985). And, uninformed voters can learn from polls of<br />

informed voters (McKelvey and Ordeshook 1986).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!