04.10.2015 Views

ECONOMY

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

donald g. saari 403<br />

Next, add “configurations of preferences” to alter the positional outcomes but<br />

not the Borda and pairwise outcomes. According to the above, we must add NRR<br />

reversal terms. To make C the plurality winner, add (see Figure 22.4b) y units of<br />

(A ≻ B ≻ C, C ≻ B ≻ A) andz units of (C ≻ A ≻ B, B ≻ A ≻ C). According to<br />

Figure 22.4b, the plurality (s = 0) tallies for A: B: C are 1 + y :2+z : y + z. Sothe<br />

C ≻ B ≻ A plurality ranking occurs with y and z values satisfying:<br />

y + z > 2+z > 1+y.<br />

One solution has y = z = 3; along with the above x = 2, they create the Chair profile.<br />

Only the Borda Count satisfies both NRR and NCR, so only this rule is immune<br />

to these perturbations: the Borda ranking remains B ≻ A ≻ C. Notice that we<br />

could have selected any ranking for the plurality method and created a supporting<br />

profile.<br />

Some consequences. Several consequences follow from this construction including<br />

the historical debate whether the Condorcet or Borda winner better reflects the voters’<br />

beliefs. As indicated above, all possible differences in the Borda and Condorcet winners<br />

are caused by Condorcet terms! (This statement holds for any number of candidates.)<br />

Consequently, this two-century debate reduces to determining the appropriate outcome<br />

for the Condorcet triplet. Namely, if you support the Condorcet winner, then<br />

you must explain why the Condorcet triplet outcome should not be a tie. As I<br />

have never heard a convincing argument, I must support the Borda winner. This<br />

comparison of Borda and Condorcet winners is illustrated with the construction of<br />

the Chair election example where the bias introduced by Condorcet triplet changes<br />

the Condorcet winner from B to A.<br />

As another example, there are many papers that analyze whether a procedure must<br />

elect the Condorcet winner. To understand the results, notice from NRR that any non-<br />

Borda positional procedure, or rules using these positional procedures, cannot satisfy<br />

this condition because their outcomes are changed by adding profile portions with<br />

no effect on pairwise outcomes. (This comment is illustrated by the construction of<br />

the Chair example.) Because the Condorcet winner can be altered by using Condorcet<br />

triplets (or Condorcet n-tuples for n ≥ 3 candidates), only those procedures based on<br />

pairwise outcomes can possibly satisfy this condition.<br />

6 Strategic and Other Behavior<br />

.............................................................................<br />

The important Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem (Gibbard 1973; Satterthwaite 1975)<br />

shows that with three or more candidates, all “reasonable” election methods (e.g.<br />

where each candidate can be elected and we exclude dictatorial rule) allow settings<br />

where it is to the advantage of some voter to vote “strategically” rather than sincerely.<br />

By doing so, the voter ensures a personally better election outcome. But we know<br />

this; for instance, had more Nader voters voted strategically for Gore in Florida,

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!