04.10.2015 Views

ECONOMY

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

192 bicameralism<br />

5 Informational Explanations<br />

.............................................................................<br />

Another potential argument for bicameralism is that it may promote more informed<br />

legislative decision-making. Since passage is required by multiple chambers, a “twoheads<br />

are better than one” logic suggests that bicameralism should lead to better<br />

legislative decisions. Rogers (2001) attempts to formalize this logic to provide an<br />

informational rationale for bicameralism. In his model, the reconciliation of interchamber<br />

differences through a “conference” committee allows for the aggregation<br />

of information that is dispersed across chambers. 18 Since it allows the dispersed<br />

information to be aggregated, a bicameral process is less likely to produce the wrong<br />

decision than a unicameral process. In fact, information is better aggregated when<br />

the chambers have congruent preferences. Thus, Rogers presents his model as an<br />

argument for congruent bicameralism.<br />

While suggestive, Rogers’s model is restrictive, and it is unclear how well it would<br />

generalize. Each chamber is modeled as a unitary actor with an exogenously given<br />

level of information about the desirability of its policy choices. It is not clear why<br />

the dispersal of information across chambers should be so much greater than within<br />

chambers. Indeed, it is not clear why consolidating the two chambers into a single<br />

unicameral chamber does not aggregate information at least as well as the bicameral<br />

procedures.<br />

A more general analysis of the role of bicameralism in aggregating information<br />

can be grounded in models of voting under incomplete information and common<br />

values—the so-called “Condorcet jury problem.” These models seem to suggest a<br />

much more circumscribed informational benefit of bicameralism.<br />

Consider n legislators who must decide whether to choose policy 0 or policy 1.<br />

They all have a common preference for choosing the correct policy. They each get<br />

an independent signal about which policy is the common preference. We assume<br />

that each player’s signal is correct with probability apple. 19 This model predicts that the<br />

probability of making a correct decision under majority rule is an increasing function<br />

of both committee size n and signal quality apple.<br />

We can compare these results to bicameralism by dividing the n legislators into two<br />

chambers. We assume that each chamber votes via majority rule. Now the probability<br />

of making a correct decision depends on which policy is enacted when the chambers<br />

disagree. However, if the disagreement policy turns out to be incorrect, bicameralism<br />

would perform far worse due to the requirement that both chambers reach the correct<br />

decision. Thus, the probability of a bicameral correct decision is much lower than that<br />

for unicameralism since each chamber is smaller and thus more likely to produce the<br />

¹⁸ A conference committee composed of members appointed from each chamber to negotiate<br />

inter-chamber differences is a common way of ensuring that bills pass each chamber in an identical<br />

form. Typically, a conference committee produces a final bill or report which is voted up or down in each<br />

chamber.<br />

¹⁹ Allowing the signal quality to vary across individuals is unlikely to change our analysis so long as<br />

signal quality does not vary systematically across chambers in the bicameral case.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!