04.10.2015 Views

ECONOMY

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

Weingast - Wittman (eds) - Handbook of Political Ecnomy

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

412 interpersonal comparisons of well-being<br />

common to restrict the individual utilities by assuming, for instance, that consuming<br />

more of all goods is always better than consuming less.<br />

We assume that a social ranking is an ordering—a reflexive, transitive, and complete<br />

social goodness relation. A social evaluation functional is welfarist if and only<br />

if there exists a social evaluation ordering (referred to as a social welfare ordering<br />

by Gevers 1979) on the set of all possible utility vectors such that, for any profile<br />

U =(U 1 ,...,U n ) and for any two alternatives x and y, x is socially at least as<br />

good as y for the profile U if and only if the utility vector u =(u 1 ,...,u n )=<br />

(U 1 (x),...,U n (x)) = U (x) is at least as good as the utility vector v =(v 1 ,...,v n )=<br />

(U 1 (y),...,U n (y)) = U (y) according to the social evaluation ordering. Welfarism is<br />

a consequence of three axioms: unlimited domain, Pareto indifference, and binary<br />

independence of irrelevant alternatives. We now provide formal definitions of these<br />

axioms.<br />

Unlimited domain requires the social evaluation functional to produce a social<br />

ordering for every logically possible utility profile. That is, no individual utility function<br />

and no combination of such functions is excluded as a possible way of assigning<br />

individual well-being to the alternatives.<br />

Unlimited domain: The social evaluation functional generates a social ordering for<br />

every logically possible utility profile.<br />

Pareto indifference demands that if, according to a utility profile U , the individual<br />

utilities for two alternatives x and y are the same, then x and y must be equally good<br />

according to the social ranking generated by U .<br />

Pareto indifference: For all alternatives x and y and for all profiles U ,ifU (x) =<br />

U (y), then x and y are equally good for the profile U .<br />

Binary independence of irrelevant alternatives is a consistency condition that imposes<br />

restrictions across different profiles. If the utilities for two alternatives x and y<br />

are the same in two profiles U and V, then the social rankings of x and y resulting<br />

from the two profiles should be the same.<br />

Binary independence of irrelevant alternatives: For all alternatives x and y and for<br />

all profiles U and V, ifU (x) =V(x) andU (y) =V(y), then the ranking of x and<br />

y for the profile U is the same as the ranking of x and y for the profile V.<br />

For a social evaluation functional that satisfies unlimited domain, Pareto indifference<br />

and binary independence of irrelevant alternatives together are equivalent<br />

to welfarism. This result, which is implicit in d’Aspremont and Gevers (1977) and<br />

explicit in Hammond (1979), is referred to as the welfarism theorem. It requires our<br />

maintained assumption that there are at least three alternatives.<br />

Theorem 1: Suppose a social evaluation functional satisfies unlimited domain. The<br />

social evaluation functional satisfies Pareto indifference and binary independence of<br />

irrelevant alternatives if and only if there exists a social evaluation ordering of all<br />

utility vectors such that, for all alternatives x and y and for all profiles U , x is at least

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!