06.06.2013 Views

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

SAFETY-FIRST AND EXPECTED UTILITY MAXIMIZATION<br />

IN MEAN-STANDARD DEVIATION PORTFOLIO ANALYSIS<br />

David H. Pyle and Stephen J. Turnovsky *<br />

I Introduction<br />

DATING back to the original work by<br />

Markowitz and Tobin [7, 11], portfolio<br />

theory has usually followed the mean-standard<br />

deviation approach in which the investor is<br />

assumed to choose among alternative portfolios<br />

on the basis of a utility function defined in<br />

terms of the mean and standard deviation of<br />

the portfolio return. Because of the arbitrary<br />

nature of utility functions, more or less parallel<br />

with these developments there have been attempts<br />

to depart from the utility framework<br />

altogether and to invoke criteria based on more<br />

objective concepts. As the first of such objective<br />

criteria, Roy [8] suggested that investors<br />

have in mind some disaster level of returns<br />

and that they behave so as to minimize the<br />

probability of disaster. This criterion, along<br />

with some variants of it, since developed by<br />

others (Telser [10],Kataoka [5]), has become<br />

known as the safety-first criterion.<br />

As we shall see, the various safety-first criteria<br />

also lead to optimization of expressions<br />

involving the mean and standard deviation.<br />

The objective of this paper is to compare this<br />

justification of mean-standard deviation analysis<br />

with the more conventional approach based<br />

on expected utility maximization. This relationship,<br />

although hinted at, has not been systematically<br />

studied in the literature (Lintner<br />

[6],Farrar [3]).<br />

In particular we shall show that:<br />

1) In the absence of a riskless asset, a correspondence<br />

can be established between the<br />

safety-first criterion and expected utility maximization<br />

when that maximization results in<br />

concave indifference curves in the mean-standard<br />

deviation space.<br />

2) If a riskless asset is available then except<br />

in one special case the safety-first criterion does<br />

not lead to the traditional liquidity preference<br />

behavior.<br />

* We thank Gordon Pye and Paul Cootner for helpful<br />

comments on an earlier draft of this paper. Needless to say<br />

they are not responsible for any errors which may remain.<br />

II Expected Utility Maximization and the<br />

Safety-First Criteria<br />

According to the expected utility approach to<br />

mean-standard deviation portfolio analysis, the<br />

investor's problem is to select a portfolio of<br />

the available assets so as to maximize some<br />

expected utility function of the form<br />

£(«) = V(>,o-) (1)<br />

where n is the expected value and cr is the standard<br />

deviation of z, the total one-period return<br />

on the portfolio. Furthermore, this utility function<br />

has the properties<br />

^ > 0 , ^ < 0 .<br />

1. MEAN-VARIANCE AND SAFETY-FIRST APPROACHES<br />

Given positive but diminishing marginal utility<br />

of wealth and a multivariate normal distribution<br />

of returns to the available assets, V is a<br />

concave function in the (/J., O-) plane. 1<br />

Turning to the safety-first principle, we shall<br />

state the following forms where i is the subsistence<br />

or disaster level of returns and a is the<br />

probability of disaster. 2<br />

(i) min Pr(z -= z)<br />

(ii) max s subject to Pr(z ^ z) == a<br />

(m) max *i subject to Pr(z ^s) £«<br />

where Pr denotes probability.<br />

Form (i) is the objective as originally stated<br />

by Roy, while (ii) is a later version proposed<br />

in a somewhat different context by Kataoka.<br />

These alternative forms both lead to indifference<br />

curves in the (/*, o-) plane whose slopes<br />

1 The original proof that V is a concave function under<br />

these conditions was given by Tobin [11]. As Fama [2]<br />

and others have pointed out, Tobin's proof based on any<br />

two parameter distribution is only valid for the normal.<br />

Feldstein [4] has presented a counter-example of a twoparameter<br />

distribution for which V is not concave. It should<br />

also be pointed out that only in special cases will £(u)<br />

depend only on /* and a. In general it will depend on higher<br />

moments as well.<br />

'Recently Baumol [1] has suggested a related criterion<br />

in which the investor compares portfolios on the basis of<br />

M, z rather than /i, 9. Since this approach involves specifying<br />

a probability level of disaster for the individual, it effectively<br />

incorporates to some extent his preferences and therefore<br />

succeeds in narrowing down the Markowitz efficiency<br />

frontier.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!