06.06.2013 Views

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

CONSUMPTION UNDER UNCERTAINTY 315<br />

over temporal uncertain prospects is readily seen if one contrasts extreme<br />

situations. At one extreme, suppose that the indifference curves are nearly<br />

linear in the vicinity of the equilibrium point: the consumer is almost<br />

indifferent about the allocation of his total resources between Cj and c2,<br />

which are almost perfect substitutes, the curvature is close to nil, and the<br />

response of Cj to a compensated change in the rate of interest would be<br />

very large. Obviously, for such a consumer, delayed uncertainty is not<br />

appreciably different from timeless uncertainty, since the opportunity to<br />

gear ct exactly to total resources matters little to him. At the other extreme,<br />

suppose that the indifference curves are very close to right angles in the<br />

vicinity of the equilibrium point: the consumer has very exacting preferences<br />

for the allocation of his total resources between c± and c2, which<br />

are strongly complementary, the curvature is very pronounced, and the<br />

response of c1 to a compensated change in the rate of interest would be<br />

negligible. For such a consumer, delayed uncertainty is very costly, due<br />

to the imperfect allocation which it entails: the utility of a consumption<br />

plan with given present value c^ + c2(l + r)- 1 decreases rapidly when the<br />

allocation departs from the preferred proportions. Thus, as formula (2.9)<br />

shows, the aversion for delayed risks grows as curvature of the indifference<br />

loci increases, or, to use more operational terms, consumers who would<br />

respond strongly to a (compensated) change in the rate of interest are<br />

relatively better suited to carry delayed risks.<br />

The role of the other factor, the marginal propensity to consume,<br />

is again most easily understood by looking at limiting situations. If<br />

dcjdy = 0, then the optimum Cj can be chosen without exact knowledge<br />

of total resources, so that perfect information is worthless. At the other<br />

extreme, a person who wants to consume all his resources now because he<br />

derives no satisfaction from later consumption is ill-suited to bear delayed<br />

risks: since he can only afford to consume now the resources he is sure to<br />

own, the uncertain prospect carries no more utility for him than the<br />

certainty of its worst outcome. In general, the inferiority of temporal over<br />

timeless uncertain prospects will be the more severe, the larger the marginal<br />

propensity to consume (other things being equal).<br />

2.4. We now turn briefly to the case where y2 is given (say y2 = y2)<br />

and r is a random variable with density {r). Our problem is to compare<br />

timeless with temporal uncertain prospects about r. One can readily verify<br />

that the Pratt "risk-aversion function" for timeless gambles about r is<br />

—(yi — Ci)(VrrIVr)y . 14 Similarly, when a\ = (yy — c^f o> 2 , we see from<br />

(2.7) that — (y1 — ^i) 2 (Co2/t/2)^ is the appropriate corresponding meas-<br />

" Note from (A.l 1) that VT = V, (y1 — Cj) has the same sign as (y, — C[): an increase<br />

in r affects utility positively for a lender, negatively for a borrower.<br />

466 PART V. DYNAMIC MODELS

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!