06.06.2013 Views

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

world. This weak sufficiency test may be checked for any particular project<br />

by solving a linear program. Projects that do not meet this stringent criterion<br />

may still be acceptable if there is a funding program that leads to an increase<br />

in expected utility. One may verify this "stronger" sufficient condition for<br />

project inclusion by solving a concave program. A relatively simple calculation<br />

can be made to determine if a project can be excluded from consideration in<br />

the present diversified package of projects. In Exercise CR-4, the reader is<br />

asked to provide direct rules for the inclusion and exclusion of projects in<br />

terms of a simple expected utility evaluation. Exercise ME-1 illustrates a<br />

two-period consumption-investment allocation problem that can be analyzed<br />

via a static analysis. Of particular interest is the relationship between the<br />

optimal investment decision that results when the random return takes on its<br />

mean value and the optimal investment decision resulting from the stochastic<br />

problem.<br />

II. Risk Aversion over Time Implies Static Risk Aversion<br />

The paper by Fama considers a multiperiod consumption-investment<br />

problem. The consumer's objective is to make investment allocations between<br />

several random investments and consumption withdrawals in each period to<br />

maximize the expected utility of lifetime consumption. The consumer's utility<br />

function is assumed to be a strictly increasing, strictly concave function of his<br />

lifetime consumption. It is not necessary in the development to assume that the<br />

utility function is intertemporally additive. It is assumed that the markets<br />

for consumption goods are perfect. Fama then shows that the consumer's<br />

behavior is indistinguishable from that of a risk-averse expected utility<br />

maximizer who has a one-period horizon. That is, the process of backward<br />

induction may be employed to reduce the multiperiod problem into an<br />

equivalent static problem. Moreover, the maximization and expectation<br />

operations preserve the concavity of the derived utility function at each stage<br />

of the induction. Fama's presentation is in a quite general setting and the<br />

results hold if the utility function is only concave (Exercise CR-1) or if the<br />

consumer's lifetime is uncertain. The results also provide a partial multiperiod<br />

justification for the static two-parameter portfolio models described in the<br />

papers by Lintner and Ziemba in Parts II and III, respectively. The basic idea<br />

that concavity properties of dynamic models are often preserved under<br />

maximization and expectation operations is a very useful one and dates back<br />

at least to early results by Bellman and Dantzig in the 1950s concerned with<br />

stochastic dynamic programming and linear programming under uncertainty,<br />

respectively. [See Wets (1966, 1972a, b) and Olsen (1973a, b) for recent results<br />

and additional references in this area.] Such reductions allow one to develop<br />

368 PART IV DYNAMIC MODELS REDUCIBLE TO STATIC MODELS

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!