06.06.2013 Views

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Hakansson paper studies a generalization of the problem treated by<br />

Samuelson. Hakansson's assumptions regarding utility for consumption are<br />

identical to Samuelson's, except for an assumed infinite lifetime. The investment<br />

possibilities facing Hakansson's investor are, however, more general. The<br />

individual is assumed to possess a (possibly negative) initial capital position<br />

plus a noncapital steady income stream which is known with certainty. In<br />

each period, borrowing and lending at a known, time-independent rate of<br />

interest, and investment in a number of risky assets with known joint distribution<br />

of returns, are possible. As usual, the risky asset returns are assumed to<br />

be independent identically distributed (iid) over time. It is further assumed<br />

that a subset of the risky assets may be sold short. In each period, initial wealth<br />

to be consumed and invested consists of the certain income plus gross return<br />

on the previous period's investment. The objective is maximization of the<br />

expected utility of consumption over an infinite lifetime.<br />

Hakansson introduces two important and apparently realistic constraints<br />

on the risky returns and the investor's decision variables. The capital market<br />

is assumed to impose a so-called no-easy-money restriction on the risky asset<br />

returns. This restriction ensures that no mix of risky assets exists which provides<br />

with probability 1 a return exceeding the risk-free rate, and that no mix of<br />

long and short sales exists which guarantees against loss in excess of the riskfree<br />

lending rate. The consumption-investment decision variables are assumed<br />

to satisfy the so-called solvency constraint. This requires that the investor<br />

always remain solvent with probability 1, i.e., that in any period t, the investor's<br />

initial capital position plus the capitalized value of the future income stream<br />

be nonnegative with certainty.<br />

Hakansson uses the familiar backward induction procedure of dynamic<br />

programming to set up a functional equation for the optimal return function<br />

(i.e., the maximum expected utility of present and future consumption, given<br />

any value of initial wealth). Since the risky returns are iid and the lifetime<br />

infinite, the functional equation obtained is stationary over time: The optimal<br />

decision variables in period t depend only on initial wealth (in period t), on<br />

the single-period asset returns, and on the relative risk-aversion index of<br />

consumption. Hakansson's treatment of the infinite horizon dynamic programming<br />

problem is intuitively plausible, but not wholly satisfactory from a<br />

rigorous standpoint. (The results are correct, however.) First, he assumes that<br />

the optimal return function exists and satisfies the functional equation; in a<br />

totally rigorous development, these facts need proof. Next, he verifies the<br />

form of the optimal solution by direct substitution, that is, by showing that<br />

the assumed form of solution actually solves the functional equation. Here<br />

the question of uniqueness arises, and is not treated satisfactorily in the<br />

development. One way of treating the problem rigorously would be to deal<br />

first with the finite horizon problem (as Samuelson does) and subsequently<br />

INTRODUCTION 435

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!