06.06.2013 Views

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

INTRODUCTION<br />

The first part of this book is devoted to technical prerequisites tor the study<br />

of stochastic optimization models. We have selected articles and included<br />

exercises that appear to provide the necessary background for the study of<br />

the specific financial models discussed in the remainder of the book. The<br />

treatment in this part is, however, necessarily brief because of space limitations<br />

; hence the reader may wish to consult some of the noted additional<br />

references on some points.<br />

The prerequisites for an in-depth study of stochastic optimization models<br />

are expected utility theory, convex functions and nonlinear optimization<br />

methods, and the embedded concepts of dynamic programming.<br />

I. Expected Utility Theory<br />

Fishburn's article presents a concise proof of a general expected utility<br />

theorem. He considers a set of outcomes and probability distributions over<br />

outcomes. The latter are termed horse lotteries. Given a set of reasonable<br />

assumptions concerning the decision-maker's preferences over alternative<br />

horse lotteries, Fishburn demonstrates the existence of a utility function and a<br />

subjective probability measure over the states of the world such that the<br />

decision-maker acts as if he maximized expected utility. The utility function<br />

is continuous and is uniquely defined up to a positive linear transformation<br />

(see Exercise CR-2 for examples). In some cases the utility function is bounded.<br />

However, most utility functions are unbounded in at least one direction. For<br />

such utility functions horse lotteries can be constructed that have arbitrarily<br />

large expected utility and an arbitrarily small probability of receiving a<br />

positive return. Such examples are called St. Petersburg paradoxes. They are<br />

illustrated in Exercises CR-4 and ME-2. Further restrictions on the utility<br />

function result if one makes additional assumptions concerning the decisionmaker's<br />

behavior. For example, an investor who never prefers a fair gamble<br />

to the status quo must have a concave utility function (Exercise CR-1). Such<br />

investors will not simultaneously gamble and purchase insurance. Exercise<br />

CR-6 is concerned with this classic Friedman-Savage paradox; see also the<br />

papers by Yaari (1965a) and Hakansson (1970). 1 If the investor's preferences<br />

for horse lotteries are independent of his initial wealth level, then the utility<br />

function must be linear or exponential (Exercise CR-5). Similarly, if the<br />

investor's preferences for proportional gambles are independent of initial<br />

1 Throughout this book references cited by date will be found in the Bibliography at the<br />

end of the book.<br />

INTRODUCTION 3

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!