06.06.2013 Views

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

stochastic differential equations and stochastic optimal control theory, the<br />

paper may be quite intimidating upon first reading. To make the paper<br />

intelligible to readers unfamiliar with these mathematical concepts, we deviate<br />

from our previous policy of keeping formalism out of the introduction:<br />

Appendix A contains a brief, intuitive introduction to stochastic differential<br />

equations and stochastic control theory. Although not rigorous, the arguments<br />

are, hopefully, sufficiently plausible as to enable the reader to understand<br />

Merton's paper with relative ease.<br />

Merton assumes the investor's utility for lifetime consumption to be an<br />

integral of utilities for instantaneous consumption over time. This is a natural,<br />

continuous-time version of the additive utility assumption in discrete time.<br />

The general formalism of the optimal control problem is outlined first for<br />

utilities that vary arbitrarily in time and is specialized in later sections to the<br />

pure "impatience" case, as in the Samuelson and Hakansson discrete time<br />

models. Most of Merton's explicit solutions pertain to utility functions of the<br />

hyperbolic absolute risk aversion (HARA) class, that is, to the class where<br />

the reciprocal of the Arrow-Pratt absolute risk-aversion index is linear in<br />

wealth. This class contains as special cases utilities having constant absolute<br />

or relative risk aversion. The individual must decide at each point in time how<br />

to allocate his existing wealth to between consumption and investment in a<br />

number of financial assets. The risky asset returns are governed by a known<br />

Markov process. The objective is maximization of expected utility of lifetime<br />

consumption, including terminal bequests.<br />

In the spirit of dynamic programming, there exists at each time t a derived<br />

utility function for wealth w, namely, the maximum expected utility of future<br />

lifetime consumption given that wealth is w at time t. The instantaneous<br />

consumption-investment problem requires the maximization of utility of<br />

consumption and terminal wealth at time t, or rather, at an "infinitesimal"<br />

time later than t. For risky asset returns governed by a stationary log-normal<br />

process (see Appendix A), terminal wealth at the end of the "infinitesimal"<br />

time span is almost deterministic. The expected utility maximization thus<br />

involves only means and variances of risky returns, as in the Samuelson paper<br />

of Part III, Chapter 1. The portfolio selection aspect of the continuous-time<br />

consumption-investment problem is thus solved exactly using mean-variance<br />

analysis. As in the Lintner and Ziemba papers of Part III, this implies that the<br />

optimal portfolio possesses the mutual fund separation pro perty: All investors<br />

will choose a linear combination of two composite assets which are, moreover,<br />

independent of individual preferences. If there exists a risk-free asset, it may<br />

be chosen as one of the mutual funds, and all portfolios reduce to a mix of this<br />

risk-free asset and a single composite risky asset which is the same for all<br />

investors. The returns on the mutual fund are also governed by a stationary<br />

log-normal process. Note that such a result is only true in continuous time:<br />

450 PART V DYNAMIC MODELS

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!