06.06.2013 Views

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

STOCHASTIC

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

utilities having constant relative risk aversion, the optimal amount of consumption<br />

will still be proportional to wealth. The relative risk aversion of induced<br />

utility for wealth will remain constant over time. The optimal asset proportions<br />

at any time t will be independent of wealth, consumption, and past or future<br />

asset returns, and will depend only on the nature of the capital market at time /.<br />

Calculation of the optimal consumption fraction at time t will, however,<br />

generally require the solution of all "future" consumption and portfolio<br />

problems, and will thus be much more complex than in the iid case. In a recent<br />

paper, Hakansson (1971c) studied a significant generalization of his model.<br />

In Hakansson's newer paper, the individual's impatience is variable, his<br />

lifetime is stochastic, and the capital assets (both risk free and risky) change<br />

in time. The individual consumes, borrows (or lends), invests in risky assets,<br />

and purchases life insurance. For additive utilities having constant relative<br />

risk aversion, solutions are obtained for the optimal lifetime consumption,<br />

investment, and insurance-buying program. For logarithmic utilities, Miller<br />

(1974a) analyzed rigorously the optimal consumption strategies over an infinite<br />

lifetime with a stochastic (possible nonstationary) income stream and a single,<br />

safe asset. Rentz (1971-1973) has analyzed optimal consumption and portfolio<br />

policies with life insurance, for stochastic lifetimes and changing family size.<br />

Additional extensions are given by Hakansson (1969b), Long (1972), and<br />

Neave (1973).<br />

III. Models of Option Strategy<br />

In the first two chapters of Part V, the emphasis is more on questions of<br />

"preferences" than on "randomness": Probabilities play a role only as<br />

weighting factors of utility through the expected value operation. The papers<br />

in Chapters 3 and 4 seem to emphasize questions of a more "probabilistic"<br />

nature. In particular, considerations invo ving stochastic processes and the<br />

dynamical behavior of random occurrences over time assume an importance<br />

lacking in previous parts of the book. Chapter 3 deals with optimal stock or<br />

bond option strategies, and with optimal sequential strategies for divestiture<br />

of a risky asset. The first Pye paper and the Taylor paper treat bond and stock<br />

option strategies from a "stopping rule" viewpoint. In a stopping rule problem,<br />

the decision maker observes (for a cost) a stochastic process and must at any<br />

decision point choose either to continue observing for at least another period<br />

or to stop observing and take a terminal action. Upon stopping, a terminal<br />

reward is received which may include future as well as immediate payoffs.<br />

The problem is to determine when to stop so as to optimize some overall<br />

average reward function. The dynamic programming approach taken in the<br />

first two papers of Chapter 3 is common to most stopping problem situations,<br />

and many other similar applications can be treated using essentially the same<br />

438 PART V DYNAMIC MODELS

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!