06.09.2021 Views

Critical Expressivism- Theory and Practice in the Composition Classroom, 2014a

Critical Expressivism- Theory and Practice in the Composition Classroom, 2014a

Critical Expressivism- Theory and Practice in the Composition Classroom, 2014a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Emerson’s Pragmatic Call for <strong>Critical</strong> Conscience<br />

Descartes’ claim—that our m<strong>in</strong>ds are disembodied, not physical <strong>and</strong> that<br />

our bra<strong>in</strong>s are material objects, merely th<strong>in</strong>gs—has a dramatic effect on how<br />

imag<strong>in</strong>ation has been classified <strong>in</strong> modernity. He claims imag<strong>in</strong>ation does not<br />

produce “entirely certa<strong>in</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>dubitable” knowledge (1968, p. 95). Therefore<br />

he rejects imag<strong>in</strong>ation (<strong>and</strong> emotion) as essential components of rationality or<br />

human nature (1968, pp. 151-152). Rhetoricians tend to agree with Descartes<br />

that <strong>the</strong> expression of affect <strong>and</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ation is not a cognitive activity, <strong>and</strong> while<br />

<strong>the</strong>y are not separate from <strong>the</strong> m<strong>in</strong>d, <strong>the</strong>y are separate from <strong>the</strong> social realm: “key<br />

terms [of Romantic rhetoric] are solitude, spontaneity, expression of feel<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong><br />

imag<strong>in</strong>ation—all quite opposed to <strong>the</strong> rhetorician’s concern for society, planned<br />

discourse, communication, <strong>and</strong> mov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> will through reason <strong>and</strong> passion”;<br />

<strong>the</strong> received view reduces “expressivism” to a “soliloquy, not an argument, <strong>and</strong><br />

… reflection not action” (Bizzell & Herzberg, 2001, p. 995).<br />

The received view claims that “expression of feel<strong>in</strong>g <strong>and</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ation” is opposed<br />

to <strong>the</strong> rhetorical goals of “reason <strong>and</strong> passion;” however, pragmatists do<br />

not make <strong>the</strong> foundation lists move by appeal<strong>in</strong>g to “reason” because that implies<br />

<strong>the</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ation is an <strong>in</strong>nate faculty like reason <strong>and</strong> passion. Nei<strong>the</strong>r <strong>the</strong><br />

idea of antecedent thought nor <strong>the</strong> social constructionist denial of our biological<br />

human nature expla<strong>in</strong>s how our experiences of <strong>the</strong> world are <strong>in</strong>separable from<br />

our conceptualization of <strong>the</strong> world (Lakoff & Johnson, 1999, p. 509). As Lakoff<br />

<strong>and</strong> Johnson argue, <strong>the</strong> metaphoricity of language is fundamental to <strong>the</strong><br />

“sensorimotor <strong>in</strong>ferences” that m<strong>in</strong>ds use to perpetually search for relations <strong>in</strong><br />

order to classify th<strong>in</strong>gs, to describe emotions, concepts, <strong>and</strong> percepts <strong>in</strong> terms<br />

of similitude (1999, p. 555). Classical pragmatists underst<strong>and</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ation as a<br />

natural part of our cognitive network. “Imag<strong>in</strong>ation uses an organic classification”<br />

(Emerson, 1929, vol. 8, p. 29) that is part of our self-project<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>st<strong>in</strong>ct:<br />

“imag<strong>in</strong>ation exp<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> exalts us” (Emerson, 1929, vol. 8, p. 29). Imag<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

moves us from <strong>the</strong> embodied realm of self-protection; it br<strong>in</strong>gs us to new ways<br />

of liv<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> world; “imag<strong>in</strong>ation animates” (Emerson, 1929, vol.8, p. 29).<br />

Imag<strong>in</strong>ation is not a solitary or quietist concept for <strong>the</strong> classical pragmatists:<br />

“Our modes of liv<strong>in</strong>g are not agreeable to our imag<strong>in</strong>ation” (Emerson, 1929,<br />

vol.1, p. 271). Neo-pragmatists Rorty <strong>and</strong> Unger argue that pragmatism <strong>and</strong> romanticism<br />

are not opposed because both give priority to <strong>the</strong> imag<strong>in</strong>ation ra<strong>the</strong>r<br />

than to reason (Rorty, 2007, pp. 105ff). 8 “Imag<strong>in</strong>ation,” says Unger, “does <strong>the</strong><br />

work of crisis without crisis [show<strong>in</strong>g] us how we can turn what we have <strong>in</strong>to<br />

someth<strong>in</strong>g else” (2007, pp. 61-62). Emerson, like Dewey notes, “imag<strong>in</strong>ation<br />

[is] a perception <strong>and</strong> affirm<strong>in</strong>g of a real relation between a thought <strong>and</strong> some<br />

material fact” (1929, vol. 8, p. 29). 9 The imag<strong>in</strong>ation is not a discrete faculty of<br />

a static bra<strong>in</strong>; ra<strong>the</strong>r, it is <strong>the</strong> use of materiality, <strong>the</strong> transformation <strong>the</strong> material<br />

world to ameliorate environ<strong>in</strong>g conditions. The power of eloquence is that<br />

227

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!