30.12.2012 Views

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Time in the Formulation of Scientific Theory 129<br />

sulted in damage to the environment. The threat to a nature that is understood<br />

mechanically by human beings ruling over it is more likely a consequence<br />

of the dissolution of the synthesis of science and theology that still<br />

existed in Newton. 45<br />

Natural scientific, as well as theological work, takes place in a social reality.<br />

The historian John Brooke describes what this means for Newton’s<br />

work. On the one hand, Brooke points to the sociopolitical interpretative<br />

potential of Newton’s ideas; 46 and, on the other hand, he examines the<br />

merging of science and theology in Newton’s thinking. 47 He contradicts the<br />

idea that, by the end of the seventeenth century, a so-called scientific revolution<br />

caused the development of modern science, with a sharp division between<br />

philosophy and theology on the one side and natural science on the<br />

other. Indeed, Newton’s century saw an increasing differentiation between<br />

theology and science, but scientific findings were still being presented in<br />

theological terminology, and divine characteristics were still being explained<br />

in physical terms. 48 Brooke elucidates this by using Newton as an example:<br />

Newton was concerned with explaining natural phenomena as mechanical<br />

processes as well as expressions of divine will. He rejected the alternative to<br />

the latter, namely that the cause of an event is inherent to physical matter.<br />

His thinking therefore adopted an ambiguity that could lead to both theistic<br />

and deistic interpretations. 49 In his laws, Newton saw proof of the constant<br />

presence of God; however, these laws could just as easily apply to the<br />

notion of an absent clockmaker. 50 In this ambiguity, Newton’s theology also<br />

bears the seed of its own destruction: Against Newton’s will, God becomes a<br />

“god of the gaps,” who is finally dethroned by Pierre de Laplace. The fact<br />

that Newton thought the Trinitarian dogma was irrelevant 51 is consistent<br />

with the premises portrayed here. As he matured, his Arian conviction grew<br />

until he became convinced that true religion and world peace would be<br />

possible only when the doctrine of the Trinity was eradicated. 52 Correspondingly,<br />

Newton also did not develop a Christology that could have<br />

influenced his religious-philosophical thoughts in Principia and Opticks. 53<br />

The observation of societal and philosophical interconnections raises<br />

the difficult question of what actually caused what. Did the sociopolitical<br />

climate influence natural philosophy or did science influence politics? Did<br />

Newton’s image of God leave its mark on mechanics or did mechanics<br />

shape his image of God? Brooke makes a plea for the latter alternative:<br />

Newton created a God for himself according to his own understanding 54 —<br />

“[t]he rationalism characteristic of his scientific work was not so much<br />

deflected as reflected in his biblical studies.” 55 At the same time, Brooke concedes<br />

that theology influenced the concept of space and also fundamentally<br />

shaped the content of the concepts of law and force. 56 In any case, one

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!