30.12.2012 Views

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

210 chapter 4<br />

reason, be bent back onto an eternal present. One can conclude from this<br />

that an appropriate understanding of time has, so to speak, two centers—<br />

present and future—and therefore must always be interested in openness.<br />

In his account of the background of eschatological thought in the twentieth<br />

century, Ratschow identifies “a deep restructuring in the understanding<br />

of time” as the main motif. 144 This restructuring, which already began<br />

during the Age of Enlightenment, went in the direction of an orientation<br />

toward the future and took shape in a belief in progress that was influential<br />

in virtually all areas of life: “Development becomes the key that fits all<br />

locks.” 145 Wherever the enthusiasm for progress grew, tradition—and therefore<br />

even the past—lost its importance. The present also forfeited some of<br />

its significance by falling victim to the search for usable development opportunities<br />

for the future. This process was closely tied to the upswing in<br />

science and technology.<br />

The elaboration of the primacy of the future is quite visible in Western<br />

philosophy during the twentieth century. Heidegger, Bloch, and Whitehead<br />

are only three of the philosophers who also strongly influenced the eschatological<br />

thinking of Pannenberg and Moltmann. 146<br />

Amidst all the enthusiasm about the future, an important distinction in<br />

the concept of the future should not be neglected. On the one hand, future<br />

can be understood as that which results from the past and the present—<br />

thus, as an extrapolation from that which exists, that is, a prediction that<br />

can be more or less reliable. This idea forms the basis for the belief in<br />

progress. If the future were not that which is set free from existing possibilities<br />

and which can also be optimized by skillful exploitation of precisely<br />

these possibilities, then the striving for progress and world improvement<br />

would be without meaning. On the other hand, future can be understood<br />

as that which comes towards me “from what is ahead.” Time flows, then, as<br />

imagined by Augustine: from the future, through the unextended present,<br />

into the past. 147 An understanding of time defined in such a manner is particularly<br />

suitable for expressing the future’s own trait of unpredictability.<br />

While purely deterministic thinking must hold to the first-mentioned understanding<br />

(that of becoming), a more fatalistically oriented feel for life<br />

can take refuge in the second understanding (that of coming), unless it<br />

wishes to understand the future as the advent of the faithful God, as Moltmann<br />

does. 148<br />

Since these two conceptions of the future point in precisely opposite directions,<br />

they seem at first to be irreconcilable. Which of the two variants is<br />

then the more appropriate? It looks as if the first concept of the future is favored<br />

strongly by a world marked by technology and feasibility: What<br />

comes is the result of more or less well-used, actual possibilities. At first

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!