30.12.2012 Views

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

134 chapter 3<br />

forces Clarke to declare that absolute space and absolute time are necessary<br />

attributes of God’s divinity. In contrast, the primacy of wisdom in Leibniz’s<br />

concept of God leads to the idea of the beauty of preestablished harmony. 90<br />

It is God’s wise foresight that makes a corrective intervention in the mechanics<br />

of the world unnecessary. In divine wisdom, God does nothing unintentionally;<br />

all God’s actions are well founded. 91 Leibniz’s aversion to the<br />

existence of a vacuum should be understood in light of the principle of<br />

God’s wisdom—namely, the less matter that exists, the fewer objects would<br />

be available for the goodness of God. God’s work would then be incomplete,<br />

which would contravene God’s wisdom and the axiom of sufficient<br />

cause that is asserted by Leibniz. 92<br />

In his second reply, Clarke concedes that the continual need to repair<br />

the world’s mechanism can be understood only in relative terms. He says<br />

that what to human observation appears to be disorder is, in reality, the expression<br />

of God’s perfect idea. In the same breath, he assures the reader that<br />

God is neither “a mundane intelligence” nor “a supramundane intelligence,”<br />

but rather “an omnipresent intelligence, both in and without the<br />

world. He is in all, and through all, as well as above all.” 93<br />

In his third letter, Leibniz directly attacks Newton’s space-time concept.<br />

He considers the concept of space as “a real absolute being” 94 to be contradictory.<br />

Such space would have to be eternal and infinite, which is why it is<br />

also erroneously conceived of as God or, at least, as an attribute of God.<br />

However, because space consists of parts, it cannot belong to God in such a<br />

manner. For this reason, Leibniz explains: “As for my own opinion, I have<br />

said more than once that I hold space to be something merely relative, as<br />

time is; that I hold it to be an order of coexistences, as time is an order of<br />

successions.” 95<br />

Accordingly, space and time are not things, but rather arrangements of<br />

things. In comparison to Newton’s Principia, the emphasis of the inquiry<br />

has shifted in Leibniz and Clarke. If Newton was primarily concerned with<br />

the question of which space and time concepts are the most successful in<br />

physics, then Leibniz and Clarke are debating less about the physical implications<br />

than about the ontological question of what space and time are. All<br />

three are thus a long way from thinking that the setting of a standard for<br />

time is more a matter of convention or consensus than a question of truth<br />

or error. 96 With their assertion that space and time represent real and independent<br />

values, Newton and Clarke are in clear conflict with a conventional<br />

solution. The relativity of time and space in Leibniz, however, also should<br />

not be understood in the sense of a conventional model, because relativity<br />

does not exist in the mutual relationship of diverse possible reference systems,<br />

but rather in the relationship of the phenomena to one another in

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!