30.12.2012 Views

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

notes to chapter 3 287<br />

106. Gerhardt, Die philosophischen Schriften, 402f., sec. 49: “l’un [space] est aussi ideal<br />

que l’autre [time].”<br />

107. Gerhardt, Die philosophischen Schriften, 415, L v, sec. 104: “.l.l. pour montrer<br />

comment l’esprit vient à se former l’idée de l’Espace, sans qu’il faille qu’il y ait un Etre reel<br />

et absolu, qui y réponde, hors de l’esprit et hors des rapports. Je ne dis donc point, que l’Espace<br />

est un ordre ou situation, mais un ordre des situations.l.l.l. Ainsi c’est quelque chose<br />

d’ideal .l.l.”; Alexander, ed., The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence, 89: “.l.l. the mind comes<br />

to form to itself an idea of space, and yet that there need not be any real and absolute being<br />

answering to that idea, distinct from the mind, and from all relations.l.l.l. Space is<br />

therefore something [merely] ideal.”<br />

108. Gerhardt, Die philosophischen Schriften, 415, L v, sec. 106. Gerhardt: “S’il n’y avoit<br />

point de creatures, il n’y auroit ny temps ny lieu; et par consequent point d’espace<br />

actuel.l.l.l. Ainsi je n’admets point ce qu’on avance icy, que si Dieu seul existoit, il y auroit<br />

temps et espace, comme à present. Au lieu qu’alors, à mon avis, ils ne seroient que dans les<br />

idées, comme les simples possibilités.”<br />

109. Alexander, ed., The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence, 104, C v sec. 45: “And when,<br />

according to the analogy of vulgar speech, we say that he exists in all space and in all time;<br />

the words mean only that he is omnipresent and eternal, that is, that boundless space and<br />

time are necessary consequences of his existence; and not, that space and time are beings<br />

distinct from him, and IN which he exists.”<br />

110. Thus, for example, von Weizsäcker, Zeit und Wissen, 354, Coveney and Highfield,<br />

The Arrow of Time, 39. Around two hundred years later, John C. Squire (1884–1958) added:<br />

“It did not last: the devil howling Ho, / Let Einstein be, restored the status quo” (according<br />

to Coveney and Highfield, The Arrow of Time, 68).<br />

111. See pp. 41–44, 65–80.<br />

112. Cf. pp. 37–44.<br />

113. Alexander, ed., The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence, 166f. (General Scholium).<br />

114. Ibid., L v, sec. 72, 80; cf. Gerhardt, Die philosophischen Schriften, 408, “determiné<br />

par des raisons internes.”<br />

115. Jüngel, Gott als Geheimnis der Welt, 36–43; trans., God as the Mystery of the World,<br />

29–34.<br />

116. One should note in this regard that Newton’s concept of God is basically less static<br />

than that of Descartes. Whereas Descartes considers God’s unchangeability to be central<br />

as the guarantee for the cognition processes within a mechanistic explanation of the world,<br />

Newton allows God to exert influence on world events by making God—though in untenable<br />

manner, as would soon be shown—responsible for the stability of the planetary system,<br />

for the “winding of the world’s clock,” and for occasional corrections.<br />

117. Alexander, ed., The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence, 168 (General Scholium); Newton,<br />

Isaac Newton’s Philosophiae Naturalis, ii, 762: “Deus nihil patitur .l.l.”<br />

118. Alexander, ed., The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence, xl–lv, offers a summary of the<br />

most important positions in the discussion of time and space extending from Leibniz to<br />

Kant and also including Mach and Einstein.<br />

119. On this, cf. Manzke, Ewigkeit und Zeitlichkeit, 85–160, who presents the developmental<br />

stages of Kant’s theory of time in detail primarily using the Inaugural Dissertation<br />

from 1770 and the Kritik der reinen Vernunft under the title “Die von der Relation zur<br />

Ewigkeit ‘befreite’ Zeit” (Time “Liberated” from the Relation to <strong>Eternity</strong>).<br />

120. “.l.l. eine notwendige Vorstellung, die allen Anschauungen zum Grunde liegt,”<br />

Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, B 46; trans., Critique of Pure Reason, 86.<br />

121. Manzke, Ewigkeit und Zeitlichkeit, 55ff.<br />

122. Alexander, ed., The Leibniz-Clarke Correspondence, xlvif.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!