30.12.2012 Views

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

220 chapter 4<br />

But how can something not yet exist and yet already exist? Is this not a paradox<br />

that one simply has to accept, unless, for the sake of intellectual honesty,<br />

one merely rejects it altogether?<br />

One way out would be to declare that this dilemma is only an apparent<br />

contradiction. Ratschow chooses this solution when he presents the view<br />

that the paradoxical relation of the “already” and the “not-yet” has in fact<br />

nothing to do with temporal categories. In his opinion, the issue instead<br />

concerns the relationship of hiddenness and clarity. 183 Ratschow thus attempts<br />

to circumvent aspects of time by making eschatology a question of<br />

hiddenness and unveiled emergence. This combination is distinguished<br />

from the concepts of promise and fulfillment inasmuch as that which is<br />

promised actually already exists. The End Time has dawned, but is hidden.<br />

The obvious strength of this approach consists in detemporalizing the problems<br />

by elevating them beyond a merely linear understanding of time without<br />

thus succumbing to an existential reduction, that is, an exclusive focus<br />

on the moment of individual existence. Furthermore, this also takes into account<br />

the insight that time cannot simply be abstracted, but instead has to<br />

be seen as “time for something.” The weakness of this approach, however, is<br />

its fading out of history and history’s significance. The hidden God, whose<br />

unveiled emergence must be awaited, seems to be a God who has largely<br />

been removed from history. It is also difficult to see how an “already” and a<br />

“not-yet” understood in this way can become relevant for shaping the<br />

world. If everything already exists and simply awaits its unveiling, then<br />

what could I still contribute, except perhaps the longing for my own death?<br />

With regard to a theology of time, Ratschow does not quite live up to the<br />

standards that he himself previously set. 184<br />

Moltmann’s eschatological concept in The Coming of God offers an alternative<br />

to this “unhistoricalness” in Ratschow. Without getting entangled in<br />

either individual eschatology or universal-historical eschatology, Moltmann<br />

sees in the coming God a possibility for conceiving both, i.e., of not having<br />

to sacrifice either earth for heaven or heaven for earth. 185 History does not<br />

become universal history; instead, it becomes a place of struggle and of messianic<br />

hope. For this reason, he also cannot—as Ratschow does—dismiss<br />

chiliasm as an idea that misses the basic concept of Christian eschatological<br />

thought. 186 Properly understood, chiliasm does both: It conceives of and anticipates<br />

crises of an apocalyptic nature, and it calls for responsibility for the<br />

world. Moltmann therefore also rejects the notion of a “final Big Bang” and<br />

speaks instead of a chiliastic eschatology of transition. This model has<br />

strengths in that it mercilessly criticizes various types of millenarianism by<br />

claiming responsibility for the world, precisely in the face of the eschaton,<br />

and by overcoming individualistic salvation by means of social physicality. 187

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!