30.12.2012 Views

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

Time&Eternity

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

218 chapter 4<br />

ing of what time is. This means that it would be a bottleneck that, from the<br />

very outset, would necessarily lead to false results if one wanted to base theological<br />

reflections about death and resurrection on a purely chronologicallinear<br />

understanding of time. That the idea of a preserved identity cannot<br />

simply and exclusively be tied to the continuity of time is, according to this<br />

view, an important insight. Precisely this happens in the notion of the immortality<br />

of the soul, however. Circumscribing death with the words “to<br />

step out of time” [att gå ur tiden], which is customary in Swedish, proves to<br />

be an appropriate reference to discontinuity. From the human perspective<br />

of our dependence upon time, death must be described as non-relationality,<br />

173 as well as complete deprivation, and thus also as deprivation of the<br />

self. The person who has died is deprived of her self. What she will be, she<br />

cannot make; she can only receive it. And, thus, as my third point, I return<br />

to Mahlmann’s feeling of unease about the possibility of preserving identity<br />

in the memory of an Other (in this case, in the memory of God). In contrast<br />

to Mahlmann, I see the great advantage of this model precisely in this<br />

relationship to an Other, since, here, one finally takes relationality and alterity<br />

seriously. Mahlmann, on the other hand, makes the possibility of<br />

eternal life dependent “upon a human existence—independent of another<br />

person’s knowledge, but self-known—that continues beyond the person’s<br />

death,” 174 an existence that is also continuously bound to a timeline. Due to<br />

its fixation on self-known existence, this eschatological model remains anthropocentrically<br />

restricted from the very outset and thus leaves little room<br />

for cosmic dimensions.<br />

In contrast, I would propose to understand eschatology as a hope that is<br />

precisely not hope in oneself. The preserved identity does not lie in a static<br />

conservation of one’s own sameness along an infinite timeline, but is rather<br />

found in relation to the Other—or, to use Ricoeur’s terminology again,<br />

when the immortality of the soul is made the precondition for eternal life, it<br />

seems to me that preserved identity is understood in the sense of mêmeté, of<br />

Idem-Identity, while the understanding that I am proposing goes more in<br />

the direction of ipséité, selfhood or Ipse-Identity. 175 I do not see this selfhood<br />

as being constituted primarily through self-conservation, but rather<br />

through self-reception, that is, through receiving one’s self. Only in this way<br />

is it completely possible to come to oneself and to find oneself; and, indeed,<br />

eternal life then presumably has to do with finding more than one’s self.<br />

Identity thus becomes a question of relation. If death and eternal life are described<br />

as that through which one’s life or self finds itself eternally, 176 then<br />

the basic assertion that God is love is violated, for love is inconceivable<br />

without alterity, without a dynamic giving and receiving. Without surrender<br />

and letting go of oneself, selfhood is impossible. Thus, the key to pre-

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!