08.06.2013 Views

Rethinking the Welfare State: The prospects for ... - e-Library

Rethinking the Welfare State: The prospects for ... - e-Library

Rethinking the Welfare State: The prospects for ... - e-Library

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Rethinking</strong> <strong>the</strong> selfare state 76<br />

assistance from private legal service providers. Our objective in this chapter will be to<br />

consider <strong>the</strong> advantages, if any, which a tied demand-side subsidy program offers over<br />

<strong>the</strong> alternatives, and to examine <strong>the</strong> design challenges encountered by voucher initiatives<br />

in this policy area.<br />

<strong>The</strong> rationales <strong>for</strong> government intervention<br />

It is crucial to note that <strong>the</strong> normative rationale invoked to justify <strong>the</strong> provision of legal<br />

services and <strong>the</strong> actual range of legal services provided are intrinsically linked. Positive<br />

egalitarian positions which hold that equal access to justice in all its <strong>for</strong>ms is a basic right<br />

will necessarily entail demands <strong>for</strong> a far more comprehensive menu of publicly provided<br />

legal services than will <strong>the</strong> minimalist libertarian position that <strong>the</strong> state should avoid<br />

interfering in <strong>the</strong> lives of its citizens to <strong>the</strong> greatest extent possible. In o<strong>the</strong>r words, <strong>the</strong><br />

legal services that a state deems “essential” correlate not to some universal objective<br />

standard, but ra<strong>the</strong>r to <strong>the</strong> grounds on which <strong>the</strong> provision of legal services is justified in<br />

<strong>the</strong> first place.<br />

Thus, <strong>for</strong> instance, <strong>the</strong> Legal Action Group (LAG) in Britain, which places heavy<br />

emphasis on <strong>the</strong> “equal” qualifier of Great Britain’s policy of “equal access to justice,”<br />

argues that “[t]he ultimate policy aim must be that anyone with a legal problem has equal<br />

access to its just conclusion so that disputes are determined by <strong>the</strong> intrinsic merits of <strong>the</strong><br />

arguments of ei<strong>the</strong>r party, not by inequalities of wealth or power.” 2 Consequently, <strong>the</strong><br />

LAG recommends <strong>the</strong> inclusion of several <strong>for</strong>ms of civil litigation as an essential legal<br />

service, as well as <strong>for</strong> extensive alternative dispute resolution to remove <strong>the</strong> financial<br />

barriers to justice presented by <strong>the</strong> cost of taking matters to trial. 3 As Griffiths points out,<br />

this argument contains two hidden premises: that “legal services are a kind of wealth,”<br />

and that <strong>the</strong> state’s goal is to remedy inequalities in wealth by redistribution, to <strong>the</strong><br />

greatest extent possible. 4<br />

This justification will not be acceptable, however, in a more libertarian state, where<br />

income redistribution is not seen as a legitimate governmental objective. Such a state is<br />

more likely to emphasize guarantees of procedural ra<strong>the</strong>r than substantive equality, with a<br />

corresponding and more modest scale of public legal services. Luban, <strong>for</strong> instance,<br />

considers that since political legitimacy in such states is grounded on <strong>the</strong> notion of<br />

“equality-of-rights-not-<strong>for</strong>tune,” <strong>the</strong> primary purpose of access to legal services is to<br />

assure <strong>the</strong> basic equality of legal rights. 5 This argument is consistent with <strong>the</strong> influential<br />

doctrine of Rawlsian liberalism which holds that <strong>for</strong>mal equality (fairness in procedure)<br />

as opposed to substantive equality (equality of outcome) should be <strong>the</strong> guiding principle<br />

of <strong>the</strong> just society. 6 O<strong>the</strong>r positions (e.g. civic republicanism and communal liberalism)<br />

exist along <strong>the</strong> spectrum between <strong>the</strong> fairly radical stances of egalitarians and libertarians.<br />

Such normative nuances account, in large part, <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> variety of legal aid policies in<br />

place around <strong>the</strong> world, and make <strong>the</strong> comparison of different systems more challenging.<br />

<strong>The</strong>re are three broad notions, however, present to varying degrees in most programs<br />

of justification <strong>for</strong> government intervention in <strong>the</strong> provision of legal services: <strong>the</strong><br />

importance of equal access to <strong>the</strong> justice system from <strong>the</strong> point of view of liberal values<br />

and social solidarity; <strong>the</strong> necessity of access <strong>for</strong> <strong>the</strong> survival of <strong>the</strong> rule of law itself; and<br />

<strong>the</strong> role that <strong>the</strong> justice system plays in establishing and maintaining patterns of resource

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!