01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

104 Antinomy of Division<br />

why it is an accident not of the body as a whole but of its parts is not<br />

explained. The commentators agree with Kant on this in as much<br />

as they find this relationship unproblematical. Bennett, for<br />

instance, who seldom does not object to what Kant says, is in this<br />

case in full agreement: "It is obviously true that a substance exists<br />

independently of any facts about how it relates to anything else to<br />

compose a larger whole ... " 60<br />

In the Monadologia physica Kant had equated "divisible" with<br />

"compounded" with regard to matter, as if only that which already<br />

consists of parts is divisible. 61 This position (though with critical<br />

restrictions) is still taken in the Critique of Pure Reason and the<br />

Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science. For space, on the<br />

other hand, the parts are not conditions of the whole; a space is not<br />

composed of its parts. "Space should properly be called not compositum<br />

but totum since its parts are possible only in the whole, not the<br />

whole through the parts" (B466). 62 Kant makes no attempt in the<br />

Critique of Pure Reason to justify the assertion that dividing up a<br />

whole does not thereby create the parts in the first place, but rather<br />

traces and displays the already existing dividedness (makes it an<br />

object of experience).<br />

I do not wish to problematize the relation of part and whole<br />

any further at this point; it will be dealt with in great detail in the<br />

next chapter. I want only to point out that Kant assumes his conception<br />

of this relation without argument. And in case it really is supposed<br />

to be self-evident, then it must at some point in time have<br />

become evident. Aquinas, for instance, did not believe that the parts<br />

were the condition for the whole. 63 Descartes considered extended<br />

matter to be a continuum that was only divided up into bodies by<br />

60 Bennett, Dialectic, p. 164.<br />

61 Monadologia physica, propositions 2 and 4 W 1,522, 528; Ak 1,477, 1,479 Cf.<br />

Adickes, Kant als Naturforscher, vol. 1, p. 149; Kemp Smith Commentary, p. 489;<br />

Prolegomena §52b.<br />

62 Although Kant does say (B211, B463) that a space consists of other spaces (and<br />

not of points or simple parts), nonetheless, the subspaces are not conditions or<br />

grounds of the space.<br />

63 Aquinas sees the conditioning of the whole by the parts as a proof that the whole<br />

in question is not a natural object. A number of houses may make up a city or the<br />

composition of parts may make up a house; these however are not natural objects<br />

but products of humans; cf.Summa contra gentiles, IV,35,3, §3731. A natural object<br />

is constituted by form and matter, and the form depends on the position or place of<br />

the object in nature. Cf. Werner, Thomas, vol. II, 201ff.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!