01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Infinite Judgments 69<br />

normally rendered in English as "indefinite terms"). "Infinitum" is<br />

the Latin translation introduced by Boethius of the Aristotelian<br />

!"#$%&"', which was applied to parts of a judgment. However, after<br />

Boethius a judgment in which either subject or predicate contained<br />

a negation was often called "affirmatio infinita" or "negatio<br />

infinita". Kant seems however to have been the first to take the term<br />

"infinitum" literally. For most logicians the expression seems to<br />

have been simply a perhaps unfortunate but traditional term for<br />

indefinite predicates or for judgments containing such predicates. 21<br />

Hegel remarked, looking back, "The name, infinite judgment, tends<br />

to be mentioned in the usual logic books, although it is not clear<br />

what its significance might be." 22<br />

Meier's Logic, which Kant used as a text in his lectures, considers<br />

infinite judgments in various forms: "If there is a negation in<br />

a judgment, either in the subject or predicate or in both at once, as<br />

long as the copula is not negated, the judgment is affirmative and is<br />

called an infinite judgment (iudicium infinitum)." 23 In practice<br />

Meier treats such judgments as if they were negative.<br />

J.H. Lambert, often cited as influential for the development of<br />

Kantian logic, does not introduce infinite judgments but does consider<br />

indefinite terms (termini infiniti); he not only equates<br />

judgements containing such terms with negative judgments but<br />

even tries to reduce the latter to the former: "With regard to affirmation<br />

and negation we must note that both actually affect the<br />

predicate, and by negation the latter is transformed into a<br />

terminum infinitum." 24 This equation of negative and infinite<br />

judgments in their logical functions subscribed to by Meier and<br />

Lambert is rejected by Kant, who notes that his division of<br />

judgments "appears to depart from the technical distinctions<br />

ordinarily recognized by logicians" (B96).<br />

21 Cf. Prantl, Logik, pp. 692f; Maier, Qualitätskategorie, p. 44.<br />

22 Hegel, Logic II,324 (pt. 2, sect. 1, chap. 2, A.c.).<br />

23 Cf. Ak 16,636.<br />

24 Lambert, Organon, §144, p. 93. It is interesting to note that Lambert after<br />

equating the two goes on to make a rather elementary logical mistake, in that he<br />

not only says that two contraries "contradict" one another but also that one must be<br />

true and the other false: "Since then consequently B and Not B cannot possibly be<br />

together in one and the same subject, then ... the statements: Every A is B and<br />

Every A is not B contradict one another absolutely, and one of them is necessarily<br />

false and the other is necessarily alone true."

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!