01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

58 Antinomies of Reason<br />

shows that Kant understands something different under the term<br />

"Empiricism" than the post-Kantian tradition. In a similar vein<br />

Fichte once classified Berkeley as a materialist — which tells us<br />

more about Fichte than it does about Berkeley. It should already<br />

occasion some perplexity that Kant attributes "popularity" to the<br />

thesis position — a property that no one has ever had to accuse<br />

rationalism of acquiring. As soon as we drop the fixation on the<br />

name that Kant gives and examine the content of the position and<br />

look at the philosophers who took up this position in the course of<br />

history, the situation becomes somewhat clearer. The positions<br />

taken in the theses can, as indicated, cum grano salis all be found<br />

in the writings of Newton: 1) a finite material world in empty<br />

absolute space, 2) indivisible atoms as the ultimate components of<br />

matter, 3) "active principles" such as the human will that introduce<br />

new force into the material world and cause voluntary movements,<br />

and 4) the habitual intervention of a deity into the everyday workings<br />

of the world; all these are integral parts of Newton's cosmology. All<br />

of these positions were explicitly attacked by Leibniz in a number of<br />

writings including the published correspondence with Samuel<br />

Clarke. 6<br />

As concerns Leibniz the grain of salt is somewhat larger and<br />

harder to swallow, but many aspects of his philosophy are clearly<br />

recognizable in the antitheses. Ever since Descartes, rationalist<br />

natural philosophers had tended to see the material universe as<br />

"indefinitely" large rather than as infinite, and Leibniz, too, concurred<br />

in this, 7 so that he was actually closer to Kant's own position<br />

6 The Newtonian position is most clearly presented by Samuel Clarke in his<br />

famous exchange of letters with Leibniz. The circumstances of the correspondence<br />

as well as a number of manuscripts of Newton's containing his drafts<br />

for parts of Clarke's letters leave no doubt that Newton agrees with Clarke on all<br />

essential points. Cf. Koyré and Cohen "Correspondence"; Alexander,<br />

"Introduction"; Freudenthal, Atom, pp. 24, 78.<br />

7 Descartes makes the distinction between infinite and indefinite in a letter to<br />

Henry More (March 5, 1649; AT V, 267f.) and in the Principia, (part I §§ 26 and 27,<br />

AT VIII, 14-15). Cf. also Wilson, "Can I..." for more sources; cf. Spinoza, Renati<br />

Des Cartes Principiorum Philosophiae Pars I & II, II, Prop.6; Leibniz, Nouveaux<br />

Essais, II, 13, §21. The arguments of the rationalists are dressed up theologically<br />

and refer to the infinitude of God; but there is also a significant philosophical<br />

reason why the material universe cannot be regarded as infinite. For such rationalists<br />

as Descartes and Leibniz (and Kant as well) the conservation of "force"<br />

and matter in a material system constituted the foundation of all science<br />

(Descartes, Principia II §§30-36, AT VIII 56-61; Leibniz "Brevis Demonstratio"<br />

and "Dynamica" GM VI, 117ff and 440). However, the conservation of infinite

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!