01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Analysis of Purpose 43<br />

ness in order to explain them at all. Such objects of experience can<br />

only be comprehended as law governed and causally determined<br />

under certain conditions, namely, that the concept or representation<br />

of the object guided the efficient causes of the object in its production.<br />

Or as Kant puts it:<br />

Only in one case does experience lead our power of judgment to the<br />

concept of a purposiveness that is both objective and material, i.e., to the<br />

concept of a purpose of nature, namely, when we have to judge a relation of<br />

cause to effect which is such that we can see it as law-governed only if we<br />

regard the cause's action as based on the idea of the effect, with this idea as<br />

the underlying condition under which the cause itself can produce that<br />

effect. (B278; CJ, 244)<br />

Although in such a case we can comprehend the lawful character of<br />

the process only if we assume that an idea of the result guides the<br />

process, we do not assume that there really exists an understanding<br />

that has the idea. This idea is a cognitive tool of ours, it is not an<br />

intention actually supposed to be realized by any understanding<br />

agent.<br />

Relative purposiveness includes the usefulness of one thing<br />

for another. Kant speaks of the "utility" of a thing for humans and<br />

its "benefit" for other living creatures. Any thing that can serve as a<br />

means for some other thing may be said to be relatively purposive,<br />

whereby the "other thing" in Kant's examples is always an organism.<br />

Kant lists a number of such relatively purposive natural<br />

relationships, such as the benefit of sandy soil for spruce trees or of<br />

rivers for plants. He points out however that the relative purposiveness<br />

of a thing depends on the purpose-character of the creature for<br />

which it is beneficial. Only if we were to assume that the existence of<br />

certain things were a purpose of nature, would we have to consider<br />

"those natural things that are indispensable for this" as natural<br />

purposes (B282; CJ, 246). But we have no empirical or logical<br />

reasons to believe that any particular thing or kind of thing ought to<br />

exist; this applies to humans as well.<br />

The relative purposiveness of one thing for another never justifies<br />

the inference that the purposive thing can only be thought to be<br />

possible in this connection. The relative purposiveness of one thing<br />

for another is never a necessary component of the explanation of the<br />

thing's origin. "For even if there were none of that natural utility,<br />

we would find that natural causes are fully adequate to make things<br />

come out this way" (B284; CJ, 247). The origin of the sandy soil so<br />

beneficial for the spruce trees can be completely explained without

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!