01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Intuitive vs. Discursive 171<br />

powerful), then the comparison cannot give us any information<br />

about the particular peculiarity of our understanding under discussion.<br />

Thus, although the intuitive understanding in the Critique<br />

of Pure Reason and in the Critique of Judgment bear the same<br />

name — and fulfill much the same kind of function — there is no<br />

justification for attributing the properties of the intuitive understanding<br />

of the Critique of Pure Reason to that of the Critique of<br />

Judgment. The fact that Kant in §77 also calls or seems to call this<br />

intuitive understanding an "intellectus archetypus" has led many<br />

commentators even to equate this understanding with the "law<br />

giving reason" of the Critique of Pure Reason (B723), which was also<br />

accorded the same Latin binomial nomenclature in parentheses. 26<br />

Nevertheless the only thing this "intuitive," non-reductionistic<br />

contrast understanding of the Critique of Judgment has in common<br />

with God as a regulative idea of the systematic unity of nature as<br />

characterized in the Critique of Pure Reason is the Latin binomial.<br />

If one considers the contrast understanding in the Critique of<br />

Judgment to be infinite, then it is in principle unclear whether it is<br />

the quantitative limitation of our understanding or its qualitative<br />

constitution that is being made responsible for the necessity of<br />

teleological principles. 27<br />

Let us now turn to the substantial point: the mechanistic constitution<br />

of the understanding. In his argument justifying the<br />

mechanistic peculiarity of our understanding Kant compares this<br />

peculiarity to a peculiarity of our intuition which he dealt with in<br />

the Critique of Pure Reason and claims that he can argue in a similar<br />

manner in the Critique of Judgment with respect to the understanding<br />

(§77, B345-6; CJ, 289). However, a new problem arises<br />

because he has in fact already used such an analogous argument in<br />

the Critique of Pure Reason to justify a constitutive principle. In §21<br />

of the Transcendental Deduction (B145-6) Kant introduced a<br />

"peculiarity of our understanding" to explain why there are twelve,<br />

and only twelve, and precisely his twelve categories. In fact it was<br />

precisely Kant's "Copernican turn" in philosophy to derive constraints<br />

on the objects of experience from the faculty of knowledge of<br />

the cognitive subject. The subjective peculiarities of the understanding<br />

became constitutive for the objects of experience. Now Kant is<br />

26 Cf. Löw, pp. 210f; Delekat, pp. 463f; Macmillan, pp. 276 and 280.<br />

27 Düsing (p. 90n) ignores this distinction asserting that the "justification of the<br />

concept of purpose is derived from the finitude of our understanding."

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!