01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Natural Purpose 47<br />

believe, organisms are such things), then the concept of natural<br />

purpose, too, has objective reality, i.e. instantiation in experience;<br />

but we can never know this definitively, since our ability to conceive<br />

of particular objects of experience as non-intentional may change<br />

with time and the progress of science.<br />

In the central section of the Analytic (§65) Kant attempts to<br />

explain what exactly a natural purpose is supposed to be. He begins<br />

with the remark that the concept of natural purpose as something<br />

that "relates to itself as cause and effect" "is still not quite appropriate<br />

and determinate and still needs to be derived from a determinate<br />

concept" (B289; CJ, 251). Kant's "derivation" of this notion is<br />

extremely problematical, and what he must have meant by it cannot<br />

be fully explicated at this point in the analysis. I shall however quote<br />

and analyze this derivation here in order at least to make it as intelligible<br />

as possible at this stage:<br />

1) A causal connection, as our mere understanding thinks it, is one that<br />

always constitutes a descending series (of causes and effects): the things<br />

that are the effects, and that hence presuppose others as their causes,<br />

cannot themselves in turn be causes of these others. This kind of causal<br />

connection is called that of efficient causes (nexus effectivus).<br />

2) But we can also conceive of a causal connection in terms of a concept<br />

of reason (the concept of purposes). Such a connection considered as a<br />

series, would carry with it dependence both downwards and upwards: here<br />

we could call a thing the effect of something and still be entitled to call it,<br />

as the series ascends, the cause of that something as well.<br />

3) This sort of causal connection is easily found in the practical sphere<br />

(namely in art). For example, although a house is the cause of the money<br />

received for rent, yet, conversely, the representation of this possible<br />

income also caused the house to be constructed. This kind of causal connection<br />

is called that of final causes (nexus finalis).<br />

4) Perhaps it would be more appropriate to call the former causal<br />

connection that of real causes, the latter that of ideal causes, since these<br />

terms would make it clear at the same time that there cannot be more than<br />

these two kinds of causality. (B*289-290; CJ, 251-52; emphasis and<br />

numbering PM)<br />

Already in the first sentence there are unclarities: for<br />

instance, what does Kant mean by "as our mere understanding<br />

thinks"? Every kind of phenomenal causality, even "ideal" causation,<br />

is thought by the understanding. The causality of final causes<br />

is precisely the causality of an understanding, as Kant often<br />

stresses. The sense of the reference to our mere understanding in<br />

this restriction will only become clear in the resolution of the antinomy<br />

at the end of the Dialectic. But other than this, the thrust of

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!