01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Three Approaches 139<br />

ims need not contradict one another is dealt with here in two relatively<br />

clear sentences. Kant did not need to write half a book simply<br />

to repeat this. In any case it seems to me not to be a very sensible<br />

strategy of interpretation to read the Dialectic of teleological judgement<br />

as a somewhat unclear and self-contradictory repetition of a<br />

triviality. The concept of antinomy itself, as we have seen in the<br />

previous chapter, excludes the possibility of puffing up such simple<br />

mistakes into antinomies. In such cases we would be dealing with a<br />

"mere artificial illusion."<br />

However, the third and most important objection to this interpretation<br />

lies in the fact that the two maxims (R1 and R2), into<br />

which the antinomy is supposed to have been resolved, are not at all<br />

in "harmony" with one another. They are formulated as a direct<br />

contradiction. Even if it be admitted that some of Kant's later utterances<br />

about the antinomy allow or even call for Cassirer's interpretation,<br />

there still remains one fundamental problem: the contradiction<br />

involved in the formal statement of the antinomy by no means<br />

disappears simply because Kant can be interpreted as reporting that<br />

it is gone. The alleged assertion by Kant of the absence of a contradiction<br />

is hardly a solution to the antinomy. He may not simply<br />

assure us that the difficulties involved with the concept of natural<br />

purpose have disappeared. If this interpretation correctly expresses<br />

Kant's views, then Kant himself is wrong and the antinomy that he<br />

has actually presented is not at all resolved.<br />

Hegel — not the first, but certainly one of the most important<br />

proponents of this sort of interpretation — saw the problem I have<br />

sketched above quite clearly and drew precisely the same conclusion,<br />

namely, that it would be wrong to think that Kant had resolved<br />

the antinomy. He assumed, however, that Kant had not noticed that<br />

the maxims were every bit as contradictory as the constitutive principles.<br />

In the Science of Logic Hegel writes about thesis and antithesis<br />

of the antinomy: 6<br />

The Kantian solution to this antinomy is ... that therefore both must be<br />

regarded not as objective propositions but as subjective maxims; that I<br />

should on the one hand always reflect upon all natural events according to<br />

the principle of mere mechanism, but that this does not prevent me, on<br />

given occasions, from investigating some natural forms according to<br />

another principle, namely according to the principle of final causes, — as if<br />

these two maxims, which by the way are supposed to be necessary for<br />

6 Hegel, Logik, II,442-3 (pt. 2, sect. 2, chap. 3). The earliest such interpretation<br />

seems to be that of Lazarus Bendavid (1796, pp. 147-152).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!