01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Transcendental Idea of Freedom 121<br />

causality. Since nature is not a thing in itself but a phenomenon, it<br />

must have an intelligible substrate that appears. Every event has a<br />

cause in the phenomenal world that precedes it in time; but every<br />

event is also the appearance of something that lies in the intelligible<br />

world. Kant now interprets the relation of a thing in itself to its<br />

appearance as a kind of cause and effect relation and speaks of the<br />

"intelligible cause of appearances" (B566). "Such an intelligible<br />

cause is not determined with respect to its causality by appearances,<br />

although its effects appear and thus can be determined by other<br />

appearances" (B*565). Every event, every link in the causal chain of<br />

phenomena, thus has two causes: a phenomenal cause preceding it<br />

in time and a noumenal cause that appears in it. The inhabitants of<br />

the intelligible world, that "underlie" the successive links of the<br />

phenomenal causal chain, are completely independent of one<br />

another, since they are neither spatio-temporal nor need they fall<br />

under the categories. If human agents should possess a faculty that<br />

is only supersensible, such as freedom, then this faculty could also<br />

"appear," that is, be the cause of an effect in the phenomenal world.<br />

"Thus the effect can be free in respect of its intelligible cause, and at<br />

the same time in respect to appearances be regarded as their result<br />

according to the necessity of nature" (B*565). The notion, Kant concludes,<br />

that there could be "natural causes" (like humans), that<br />

"have a faculty which is intelligible only" (like freedom) is compatible<br />

with the "law of causality" as long as the phenomena of these<br />

intelligible causes agree with the causal laws (B573). What Kant<br />

seems to mean is that the moral ought of freedom 87 could appear as<br />

an empirical willing to carry out this or that action in the phenomenal<br />

world. At least this can be conceived without contradiction.<br />

With this 'proof' Kant has of course proved much too much.In<br />

this sense every event can be called free. About things in themselves<br />

we cannot affirm or deny anything determinate except how they<br />

87 The precise mechanism of the causality of intelligible freedom in the material<br />

world is not described by Kant. From some remarks in connection with the Fourth<br />

Antinomy is becomes clear that a phenomenal action itself is not to be considered<br />

the appearance of freedom as a thing in itself. Kant distinguishes between the<br />

ground of the existence (Fourth Antinomy) and the ground of the causality (Third<br />

Antinomy) of a phenomenon (B446, B589). The construction seems to be as<br />

follows: the free arbitrary will (noumenon) follows a moral rule; this decision<br />

appears as empirical arbitrary will (arbitrium brutum) to perform a certain<br />

action, thus bringing it about. Thus freedom is the ground of the causality of the<br />

empirical willing of an action. Cf. also CJ, Blv; W 5,271)

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!