01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

136 Antinomy of Judgment<br />

we cannot explain mechanistically need we take refuge in teleology.<br />

The maxim of teleology proper ("Judging them requires a quite different<br />

causal law — viz., that of final causes") is introduced only if<br />

the first part of (R2) is true; and furthermore, it can only then potentially<br />

lead to difficulties if (R1) is also true. Thus a conflict between<br />

mechanism and teleology can only then arise when both apparently<br />

contradictory propositions about mechanism are true, that is, after<br />

the antinomy proper has already been resolved in a "subcontrary"<br />

manner. The resolution of the apparent contradiction must show<br />

that both maxims of mechanism can in some intelligible sense be<br />

said to be true. After the resolution of the antinomy proper, the occasional<br />

use of teleology must then be reconciled with what is left of<br />

mechanism. The first task is completed by Kant in the second to the<br />

last section, §77; the second task in the last section, §78. It is essential<br />

for an understanding of the Kantian text to remember that we<br />

are dealing with three propositions (two on mechanical laws and<br />

one on final causes) and with two different oppositions. The two<br />

propositions about mechanism contradict one another; their relation<br />

to the proposition about final causes has still to be clarified.<br />

Kant's presentation of the antinomy in §70 takes these three<br />

elements and their particular relations into account. Before he cites<br />

the maxims themselves, he examines their origins. He stipulates:<br />

that judgment presupposes two maxims as it reflects: one of these the mere<br />

understanding gives it a priori; the other is prompted by special<br />

experiences, experiences that bring reason into play so that we may judge ...<br />

in terms of a special principle. (B314; CJ, *267; emphasis PM)<br />

Mere understanding says "everything must"; special experience<br />

says "some things cannot"; and then reason comes into play and in<br />

turn introduces final causes. Three elements are mentioned: 1)<br />

understanding a priori, 2) empirical understanding or experience,<br />

and 3) reason. At this point in the analysis it is difficult to explain<br />

what exactly these distinctions are supposed to mean. However, it<br />

can at least be pointed out that we have already encountered a similar<br />

distinction between understanding and reason in the "derivation"<br />

of the concept of natural purpose in §65. There, the "mere<br />

understanding" prescribed a particular kind of causal connection; a<br />

special experience compelled the understanding to introduce final

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!