01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

If , however, we replace (2) with the infinite judgment:<br />

3a) The world is non-infinite (i.e. finite),<br />

Tertium datur 77<br />

we obtain a contrary opposition because (3a) says "more" than is<br />

necessary for contradiction with (1). The Law of the Excluded<br />

Middle applies to the conjunction of (3) and (1) — and (1) and (3a) —<br />

only if the world belongs to the genus of things that have a<br />

determinate size, either finite or infinite. Kant maintains that in<br />

order to have some determinate or definite magnitude, the world as<br />

a whole would have to be able to be given as a totality — which, he<br />

maintains, could occur only if it were a thing in itself. Thus only on<br />

the assumption that the world is a thing in itself does the thesis of<br />

the First Antinomy contradict the antithesis in the strict sense. If I<br />

deny this assumption, then the two propositions turn out to be mere<br />

contraries. 36<br />

If, therefore, we say, "the world is either infinite in extension or it is not<br />

infinite (non est infinitus)," and if the former proposition is false, its contradictory<br />

opposite, "the world is not infinite," must be true. And I should thus<br />

remove [aufheben] an infinite world, without positing [setzen] another,<br />

namely, a finite world. But if we had said, "the world is either infinite or<br />

finite (non-infinite)," both statements might be false. For in that case we<br />

should be regarding the world in itself as determined in its magnitude, and<br />

in the counterproposition we do not merely remove the infinitude, and with<br />

it perhaps the entire separate existence of the world, but attach a determination<br />

to the world as a thing real in itself. This assertion may, however,<br />

likewise be false, if, namely, the world is not given as a thing in itself at all<br />

and thus not given as either infinite or finite with regard to size. I beg permission<br />

to entitle this kind of opposition dialectical opposition, and that of<br />

contradiction analytical opposition. Thus of two dialectically opposed<br />

judgments both may be false due to the fact that the one does not merely<br />

contradict the other, but says something more than is required for contradiction.<br />

(B*531-2)<br />

36 Wolff interprets this passage as follows. "Kant thus maintains that the relation<br />

of the predicates 'infinite' and 'finite' is always contrary, while the relation<br />

of the predicates 'infinite' and 'not infinite' is always contradictory. Kant seems<br />

once again to attempt to base the contrariety between 'finite' and 'infinite'<br />

independent of context on purely linguistic critieria." (Der Begriff, 54) While it is<br />

true that Kant does indeed try to base the opposition of these predicates on purely<br />

linguistic criteria, 1) both pairs of oppositions are considered to be 'contradictory';<br />

2) Wolff ignores Kant's explicit distinction between "not infinite [nicht<br />

unendlich] (non est infinitus)" and "non-infinite [nichtunendlich]"; in the first<br />

expression the negation is part of the copula, in the second part of the predicate; 3)<br />

here, Kant is dealing not with problems involving the oppposition of predicates but<br />

of judgments: affirmative and infinites judgments are contraries; affirmative<br />

and negative judgments are contradictories.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!