01.05.2013 Views

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

KANT'S CRITIQUE OF TELEOLOGY IN BIOLOGICAL EXPLANATION

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Transcendental Idea of Freedom 123<br />

find no ground for thinking that any faculty is conditioned otherwise<br />

than in a merely sensible manner" (B574). Whatever may later be<br />

the case, at least in the Critique of Pure Reason Kant sees no special<br />

connection between freedom and the organism.<br />

2) Thus far it has only been said that humans have empiricaltheoretical<br />

knowledge of themselves as causally determined inhabitants<br />

of the Leibnizian realm of nature and apperceptive access to<br />

themselves as inhabitants of the Leibnizian realm of grace, and that<br />

the supersensible can without contradiction be conceived as the<br />

cause of appearances. The second ground that Kant adduces for<br />

singling out freedom, reads: "'Ought' [Sollen] express a kind of<br />

necessity and of connection with grounds which is found nowhere<br />

else in the whole of nature" (B575). The real sense of Kant's appeal<br />

to "imperatives" in this context becomes clearer through the explanations<br />

that he gives in the introduction to the Critique of<br />

Judgment. There he again distinguishes between nature and freedom,<br />

and twice stresses that nature cannot influence freedom (the<br />

reverse is not asserted). However, even if the physical cannot act<br />

upon the moral, nonetheless the moral ought to act on the physical<br />

and consequently this action must be conceivable:<br />

Hence an immense gulf is fixed between the domain of the concept of<br />

nature, the sensible, and the domain of the concept of freedom, the supersensible,<br />

so that no transition from the sensible to the supersensible (and<br />

hence by means of the theoretical use of reason) is possible, just as if they<br />

were two different worlds, the first of which cannot have any influence on<br />

the second; and yet the second ought to have an influence on the first, i.e.,<br />

the concept of freedom ought to actualize in the world of sense the purpose<br />

enjoined by its laws. Hence it must be possible to think of nature as being<br />

such that the lawfulness in its form will harmonize with at least the<br />

possibility of the purposes that we are to achieve in nature according to the<br />

laws of freedom. (Bxixf; CJ, *14-15)<br />

It is the moral ought that is meant here. Kant's reasons for<br />

attributing causality in the material world to moral freedom, that is,<br />

for assuming a cosmological or transcendental freedom, are moral.<br />

He attempts to show that this transcendental idea of freedom is logically<br />

possible, apperceptively accessible, and furthermore morally<br />

"necessary." 89<br />

89 Compare this position with that of the key sentence of the so-called "oldest<br />

system program" of German Idealism: "How must a world be constituted for a<br />

moral being?" Kant wanted only to prove the conceptual possibility of what<br />

morality demands; his successors, however, drew conclusions about the nature of<br />

the material world from the fact that moral agents can act in this world.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!