09.11.2014 Views

SEEU Review vol. 5 Nr. 2 (pdf) - South East European University

SEEU Review vol. 5 Nr. 2 (pdf) - South East European University

SEEU Review vol. 5 Nr. 2 (pdf) - South East European University

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>SEEU</strong> <strong>Review</strong> Volume 5, No. 2, 2009<br />

Justice and Fairness<br />

In the first formulation of justice as fairness it is stated that the decisive<br />

part of the concept of justice is fairness. Justice is claimed as a virtue of the<br />

institutions and practices, and the principles of justice are considered as<br />

formulating restrictions for the institutions that define the authority, powers,<br />

liabilities, rights and duties (Rawls, 1999, 47). However, Rawls confines<br />

himself to the sense of justice in relation to practices. It is not a<br />

comprehensive view of good society but a part of it. He just focuses on the<br />

common sense of justice, which requires a balance between competing<br />

considerations.<br />

For Rawls, fairness refers to “right dealing between persons who are<br />

cooperating with or competing against one another”. The question of fairness<br />

emerges when free and equal persons engage in a joint activity whose rules<br />

are defined and accepted by them and determine the respective shares and<br />

burdens. The practice is fair since nobody obtains illegitimate advantages.<br />

One sees a claim as legitimate when everybody in the practice acknowledges<br />

it as reasonable. A fair practice supports respective positions against the<br />

background of the mutual understanding of the principles by free persons<br />

who are equal as regards with authority (Rawls, 1999, 59). A true<br />

community presupposes mutual acknowledgments of principles. In addition,<br />

fairness applies to the <strong>vol</strong>untary practices (like in games and business<br />

competition) whereas justice to the practices where there is no option to<br />

enter (like in slavery) (Rawls, 1999, 59).Therefore, to change unjust<br />

practices is more urgent in order to change unfair ones (Rawls, 1999, 60).<br />

In a fair practice, parties acknowledge a “prima facie duty” against each<br />

other and corresponding “prima facie right” in tune with the practice. One<br />

whose liberty is restricted because of the rules of practice he entered into has<br />

the right over the others who benefit from his submission to the restriction. It<br />

is the consequence of a fair practice (<strong>vol</strong>untarily undertaken) from that each<br />

person benefits. The rights and duties here are not the obligatory results of a<br />

contract or promise but they are based on “previous actions <strong>vol</strong>untarily<br />

undertaken, in this case on the parties having engaged in a common practice<br />

and knowingly accepted its benefits”. Political obligation does not suppose<br />

<strong>vol</strong>untary act as it is thought in the social contract theory. Fairness apples to<br />

<strong>vol</strong>untary practice while justice to in<strong>vol</strong>untary one. In the former, “prima<br />

facie obligation” may be overridden whereas in the latter, one can not escape<br />

from the obligation only because obedience is required. Otherwise, the<br />

11

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!