27.06.2015 Views

3071-The political economy of new slavery

3071-The political economy of new slavery

3071-The political economy of new slavery

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

190 <strong>The</strong> Global Framework for Development<br />

Development ethics as global ethics<br />

If our goal then is the alleviation <strong>of</strong> extreme poverty, all the above questions<br />

are relevant at all levels and in all areas. <strong>The</strong>y apply to all kinds <strong>of</strong><br />

agents: individuals and organizations in rich countries, individuals and<br />

organizations in poor countries, rich governments, poor governments,<br />

NGOs, business companies, international organizations. This is because<br />

the way in which people make their decisions in terms <strong>of</strong> the ethical<br />

criteria involved make some difference to what happens directly or<br />

indirectly vis à vis extreme poverty. Development ethics needs to focus<br />

more than it has on some <strong>of</strong> these questions.<br />

I focus on one or two <strong>of</strong> these questions, without attempting to cover<br />

the whole field. My suspicion is that a disproportionate amount <strong>of</strong><br />

intellectual energy has actually been poured into the debate about the<br />

right theory <strong>of</strong> value underlying development – the debate between neo-<br />

Aristotelians, Kantians, human rights thinkers and so on. This debate<br />

is important, and in some cases adopting one approach as opposed to<br />

another may result in different policy recommendations.<br />

But these differences are little compared with the general differences<br />

between these positions and a conventional approach to development,<br />

which is more dominated by economic growth assumptions. Critiques <strong>of</strong><br />

the latter can be mounted from any <strong>of</strong> the ethically enriched positions.<br />

A similar issue exists in connection with environmental ethics: much<br />

intellectual energy is expended on the debates between biocentrists,<br />

ecocentrists and enlightened anthropocentrists (who accept the de facto<br />

ecological limits), though all <strong>of</strong> them have powerful arguments against<br />

the conventional and shallow anthropocentrism <strong>of</strong> mainstream thinking.<br />

For me the crucial challenge is the construction <strong>of</strong> an adequate global<br />

ethic for the twenty-first century – a global ethic which both informs<br />

what individuals do and how they perceive themselves, and also informs<br />

our understanding <strong>of</strong> international relations and the norms that should<br />

guide states and economic actors, and reflects the changing realities <strong>of</strong> our<br />

increasingly globalized world. <strong>The</strong>se concerns may seem far away from<br />

the concerns <strong>of</strong> poverty alleviation, and yet like a boomerang, the way<br />

they are thought through and the conclusions reached have, or could<br />

have, powerful impacts on the prospects <strong>of</strong> the poor – possibly more than<br />

the outcomes <strong>of</strong> ethical debates about the good in development itself.<br />

This is relevant to the challenge <strong>of</strong> economic <strong>slavery</strong> since in many<br />

ways the key issues are about: the extent to which ethical constraints on<br />

international trade including trafficking are taken seriously; the extent<br />

to which there is or is not a relativistic acceptance <strong>of</strong> practices elsewhere

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!