15.01.2013 Views

CAPITALISM'S ACHILLES HEEL Dirty Money and How to

CAPITALISM'S ACHILLES HEEL Dirty Money and How to

CAPITALISM'S ACHILLES HEEL Dirty Money and How to

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Philosophy Becomes Culture 317<br />

Desire <strong>and</strong> Want.” 14 “The utility of a thing <strong>to</strong> a person . . . is measured by<br />

the extent <strong>to</strong> which it satisfies his wants. And wants are . . . not reckoned . . .<br />

according <strong>to</strong> any ethical or prudential st<strong>and</strong>ard.” 15 “It is clearly not the part<br />

of economics <strong>to</strong> appear <strong>to</strong> take a side in ethical controversy.” 16 In other<br />

words, what is useful is what is wanted, <strong>and</strong> ethics do not here enter in<strong>to</strong> the<br />

calculation.<br />

Marshall went on <strong>to</strong> strip away from the idea of usefulness <strong>and</strong> advantage<br />

any uncertainty as <strong>to</strong> its appropriate yardstick: “ ‘[M]oney’ or ‘general<br />

purchasing power’ or ‘comm<strong>and</strong> over material wealth’ is the centre around<br />

which economic science clusters; . . . not because money or material wealth<br />

is regarded as the main aim of human effort, . . . but because in this world<br />

of ours it is the one convenient means of measuring human motive on a<br />

large scale.” 17<br />

Much of Marshall’s Principles of Economics was taken up with earnest<br />

moralizing <strong>and</strong> technical footnotes, including a mathematical appendix<br />

on methods of analysis. Commenting on Marshall, F.Y. Edgeworth, an<br />

Oxford don of the time, wrote of the connection between utilitarianism<br />

as a philosophy <strong>and</strong> utility as a calculation as follows: “To procure the<br />

greatest possible sum of satisfaction for all is right. . . . There is certainly<br />

no logical connection between this principle <strong>and</strong> the economic art of<br />

measurement; <strong>and</strong> yet, as it seems <strong>to</strong> us, there is more than a verbal alliance.<br />

... [Marshall] lends the authority of an accredited science <strong>to</strong> defend<br />

at least the possibility of Utilitarian Ethics. It is not indeed<br />

demonstrated that the Utilitarian . . . principle is true, but there is created<br />

the conviction that it is not nonsense.” 18<br />

As the twentieth century progressed, Marshall’s ethical protestations<br />

were forgotten in favor of his math: “[T]he Marshallians concentrated their<br />

efforts on what they considered <strong>to</strong> be a value-free endeavour devoted <strong>to</strong> a<br />

sharpening of the analytical <strong>to</strong>ols that Marshall forged.” 19 “The precision<br />

<strong>and</strong> thoroughness of his formal analysis completely obliterated . . . his explicit<br />

policy conclusions. ... [H]is engine of analysis pressed methodically<br />

onward <strong>to</strong> construct a painstakingly elaborate, logically impregnable,<br />

supremely aesthetic edifice . . .” 20<br />

Tracing a process more than a century long, Cambridge professor Tom<br />

Warke zeros in on what began <strong>to</strong> transform a philosophy in<strong>to</strong> a science: “By<br />

what process did the utility concept in economics evolve from its Benthamite

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!