10.07.2015 Views

essential-guide-to-qualitative-in-organizational-research

essential-guide-to-qualitative-in-organizational-research

essential-guide-to-qualitative-in-organizational-research

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

–––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––– ANALYTIC INDUCTION–––––––––– 177First, a criticism of AI argues that due <strong>to</strong> the small samples used, the method can rarelymake claims about the representativeness of its samples and therefore any attempt atgeneraliz<strong>in</strong>g is tenuous. For Mitchell (1983) such a criticism shows a confusion between theprocedures appropriate <strong>to</strong> mak<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>ferences from survey <strong>research</strong> and those which areappropriate <strong>to</strong> case study work. He argues that analytical th<strong>in</strong>k<strong>in</strong>g about survey data is basedupon both statistical and logical (namely causal) <strong>in</strong>ference and how there is a tendency <strong>to</strong> elidethe former with the latter <strong>in</strong> that ‘the postulated causal connection among features <strong>in</strong> a samplemay be assumed <strong>to</strong> exist <strong>in</strong> some parent population simply because the features may be<strong>in</strong>ferred <strong>to</strong> co-exist <strong>in</strong> that population’ (Mitchell, 1983: 200). In contrast <strong>in</strong>ference <strong>in</strong> casestudy <strong>research</strong> can only be logical and derives its external validity not from itsrepresentativeness but because ‘our analysis is unassailable’ (Mitchell, 1983: 200). Suchanalytical thoroughness is achieved <strong>in</strong> AI by elim<strong>in</strong>at<strong>in</strong>g exceptions and revis<strong>in</strong>g hypothesesso that statistical tests are actually unnecessary once negative cases are removed (Field<strong>in</strong>g andField<strong>in</strong>g, 1986: 89). Thus <strong>in</strong> AI extrapolation is derived from logical <strong>in</strong>ference based upon thedemonstrated power of the <strong>in</strong>ductively generated and tested theoretical model ‘rather than therepresentativeness of the events’ (Mitchell, 1983: 190).Secondly AI’s procedures entail the movement from the ‘thick’ description andcategorization of ac<strong>to</strong>rs’ phenomenological worlds <strong>to</strong> propound<strong>in</strong>g theoretical explanationsof those categories. This entails an <strong>in</strong>itial (re)presentation of ac<strong>to</strong>rs’ <strong>in</strong>ternal logics grounded<strong>in</strong> verstehen <strong>in</strong> order <strong>to</strong> formulate categories. However, <strong>in</strong> order <strong>to</strong> avoid analytic <strong>in</strong>terruptusAI requires the <strong>research</strong>er <strong>to</strong> shift <strong>to</strong> a form of analysis that entails his/her imposition of anexternal logic which exists <strong>in</strong>dependently of, and expla<strong>in</strong>s, the ac<strong>to</strong>rs’ <strong>in</strong>ternal logics. Clearlythis shift entails an overt form of what Burrell and Morgan term ‘on<strong>to</strong>logical oscillation’(1979: 266) – the <strong>in</strong>itial adoption of a subjectivist stance with the subsequent <strong>in</strong>troduction of<strong>in</strong>commensurable objectivist assumptions. Now the question for AI is whether, as Burrell andMorgan claim (1979), such oscillation poses a contradiction which should be avoided, or asWeick (1995: 34–8) argues, such oscillation is a vital element <strong>in</strong> sensemak<strong>in</strong>g that helps usunderstand the everyday actions of people. Basically the latter view would support AI as it ispresented here, whereas the former would either necessitate the discard<strong>in</strong>g of aphenomenological start<strong>in</strong>g po<strong>in</strong>t for AI, or AI’s dissolution through a limitation <strong>to</strong>phenomenological ‘thick description’.F<strong>in</strong>ally there rema<strong>in</strong>s a basic question regard<strong>in</strong>g the extent <strong>to</strong> which ‘pure’ <strong>in</strong>duction ispossible. Ironically, the claim that it is possible shares with logical positivism the implicitassumption that there exists a theory neutral observational language <strong>in</strong> which the <strong>research</strong>eris construed as neutral conduit of cultural experience who can objectively elucidate andpresent the ‘facts’ of a cognitively accessible empirical world. For Hammersley (1992) suchissues are especially problematic for any approach which is committed <strong>to</strong> access<strong>in</strong>g members’phenomenological worlds so as <strong>to</strong> reveal their subjectivities. It creates a contradiction betweenan objectivist impulse that emphasizes how phenomenological accounts should correspondwith members’ subjectivity and a phenomenological impulse that suggests that people sociallyconstruct versions of reality – culturally derived epistemic processes <strong>to</strong> which <strong>research</strong>ers arenot immune. Perhaps a key task for any methodologist with a subjectivist agenda is <strong>to</strong> resolvethe problems posed by these epistemological ambiguities while avoid<strong>in</strong>g the spectre, andquagmire, of relativism (see Alvesson and Deetz, 2000).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!